Ethical copula, negation, and responsibility judgments | Synthese
Skip to main content

Ethical copula, negation, and responsibility judgments

Prior’s contribution to the philosophy of normative language

  • S.I. : The Logic and Philosophy of A.N. Prior
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Prior’s arguments for and against seeing ‘ought’ as a copula and his considerations about normative negation are applied to the case of responsibility judgments. My thesis will be that responsibility judgments, even though often expressed by using the verb ‘to be’, are in fact normative judgments. This is shown by analyzing their negation, which parallels the behavior of ought negation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
¥17,985 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (Japan)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A convention on the use of quotation marks: quotation marks are simple (‘ ’) only for terms used in suppositione materiali; quotation marks are double (“ ”) for all other uses: scare quotes, irony, etc. Here it is an example: ‘When talking about “use”, use ‘use”.

  2. Barcan schema dates back to 1946, but Prior’s well-known discussion of it is—as far as I know—later than his Prior (1951).

  3. On the modality vs predicate approach to necessity, see Halbach et al. (2003), Halbach and Welch (2009). Geach questioned the operator approach for deontic modality in Geach (1981).

  4. Ross (1968, §§ 31–32) noticed this with direct reference to deontic logic. It’s possible that external negation in this flavor is non-classical. I thank Olivier Roy for discussion on this point. I don’t know of any discussion of internal and external negation in hyperintensional contexts. In recent work (Faroldi ms) I have maintained that ‘ought’ creates hyperintensional contexts, not just intensional ones. By hyperintensional I mean anything finer than intensionality (defined either in terms of metaphysical or logical equivalence), ie. co-intensional expressions are not equivalent in ought contexts. The hyperintensionality of ought appear to require a stronger notion of equivalence for normative expressions, which I generically call co-hyperintensionality.

  5. Cf. Russell (1905). As far as I am aware, Frege (for instance in Frege 1918-9) did not notice this phenomenon.

  6. For instance by Horn (1989, §6).

  7. ‘True’ was proposed by Karttunen and Peters (1979).

  8. Horn (1989, Chap. 6) questions the use of ‘true’ and underlines how no known natural language employs two distinct negative operators corresponding directly to internal and external negation, even if a given language employs two (or more) negative operators, for instance (former: declarative negation; latter: emphatic negation): Ancient Greek: ‘ou’ vs. ‘mē’; Modern Greek: ‘den’ vs. ‘me’; Hungarian: ‘nem’ vs. ‘ne’; Latin: ‘non’ vs. ‘nē’; Irish: ‘nach’ vs. ‘gan’; Sanskrit: ‘na’ vs. ‘mā’. There is another ‘un-’ in English which is not a negative operator, but it is analogous to German ‘ent-’ as in ‘un-fold’, ‘ent-falten’. See Horn’s interesting list of languages with distinct negative operators at p. 366.

  9. But duplex negatio affirmat only in classical logic and some natural languages, for instance contemporary standard English. Both in Old and Middle English, along with contemporary languages such as Italian, Portuguese and many others, duplex negatio n e g a t.

  10. This cancellability feature seems to distinguish presuppositions from Gricean implicatures. Cf. Beaver and Geurts (2013, § 3). For a cutting-hedge survey on the pragmatics/semantics debate on presuppositions, see Schlenker (forthcoming).

  11. As a matter of fact this was known at least from Anselm of Canterbury. Cf. Anselm of Canterbury (1936), p. 36 and for a translation and discussion of the difference between Anselm’s debere non peccare [have not to sin] and non debere peccare [don’t have to sin] cf. Faroldi (2014b, Appendix A).

  12. External negation need not to be realized linguistically. It can also be realized metalinguistically. I discuss at length these concerns about various kinds of negation and their different uses in Faroldi (2014b, Chap. 5).

  13. Of course I am aware these are only some possible paraphrases— there might be many more. The most important fact is that internal and external negation can be consistently kept separable.

  14. That external negation of a norm is not a norm anymore (roughly) is quite pacific a thesis among moral and legal philosophers (cf. Bulygin 1985, pp. 151–152; Weinberger 1979, pp. 121–122; von Wright 1963, pp. 138–139), but contentious in deontic logic.

  15. It’s plausible that (normative) justifications are hyperintensional. This would nicely explain also the use of ‘because’ in giving justifications. I thank Paul McNamara for discussion on the point.

  16. As I noted with accusations, not all excuses are pled using a verb like ‘to excuse’ or Italian ‘scusare’; in an analogous fashion, it is not only the use of ‘to excuse’ or ‘scusare’ that can make an excuse.

  17. The results of this section partially overlap with Faroldi (2014a, Sect. 4).

References

  • Anselm of Canterbury (1936). Lambeth’s Fragments. In Ein neues unvollendetes Werk des hl. Anselm von Canterbury, ed. by Franciscus Saverius Schmitt, Münster i. W.: Aschendorff.

  • Austin, J. L. (1956). A plea for excuses: The presidential address. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 57, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beaver, D. I., Geurts, B. (2013). Presupposition. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Fall 2013

  • Bulygin, E. (1985). Norms and logic: Kelsen and Weinberg on the ontology of norms. Law and Philosophy, 4, 145–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faroldi, F. L. G. (2014a). Denial of responsibility and normative negation. In F. Cariani, et al. (Eds.), Deontic logic and normative systems (pp. 81–94). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faroldi, F.L.G. (ms) Oughts, Apples, and Popes: Normativity and Hyperintensionality, under review

  • Faroldi, F. L. G. (2014b). The normative structure of responsibility. Law, language, ethics. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1918-1919). Der Gedanke: Eine logische Untersuchung. Beiträge zur Philosophie des Deutschen Idealismus, I, 58–77.

  • Geach, P. T. (1981). Whatever happened to deontic logic? Philosophia, 11, 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V., Leitgeb, H., & Welch, P. H. (2003). Possible-worlds semantics for modal notions conceived as predicates. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 32, 179–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V., & Welch, Ph. (2009). Necessities and necessary truths: A prolegomenon to the use of modal logic in the analysis of intensional notions. Mind, 118, 71–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. R. (1989). A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, L., & Peters, S. (1979). Conventional implicature. In C.-K. Oh & D. Dinneen (Eds.), Syntax and semantics 11: Presupposition (pp. 1–56). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, F. R. (1986). Mood and modality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. (1951). The ethical copula. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 29(3), 137–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, A. (1968). Directives and norms. New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind, 14, 479–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, PH. (forthcoming). The semantics/pragmatics interface. In M. Aloni & P. Dekker (Eds.), Cambridge handbook of formal semantics, forthcoming

  • von Wright, G. H. (1963). Norm and action: A logical enquiry. New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberger, O. (1979). Logik, Semantik, Hermeneutik. München: C.H. Beck.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Previous versions of this paper received helpful feedback in Pavia and at DEON14. I heartily thank Amedeo G. Conte, Guglielmo Feis, Magdalena Kaufmann, Filippo Magni, Paul McNamara, Olivier Roy. Some results of Sect. 4 partially overlap with Faroldi (2014b, Chap. 5) and Faroldi (2014a).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Federico L. G. Faroldi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Faroldi, F.L.G. Ethical copula, negation, and responsibility judgments. Synthese 193, 3441–3448 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0911-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0911-1

Keywords