Possibility and Dyadic Contingency | Journal of Logic, Language and Information Skip to main content
Log in

Possibility and Dyadic Contingency

  • Published:
Journal of Logic, Language and Information Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper aims at developing the idea that the standard operator of noncontingency, usually symbolized by Δ, is a special case of a more general operator of dyadic noncontingency Δ(−, −). Such a notion may be modally defined in different ways. The one examined in the paper is Δ(B, A) = df ◊B ∧ (A ⥽ B ∨ A ⥽ ¬B), where ⥽ stands for strict implication. The operator of dyadic contingency (B, A) is defined as the negation of Δ(B, A). Possibility (◊A) may be then defined as Δ(A, A), necessity (□A) as (¬A, ¬A) and standard monadic noncontingency (ΔA) as Δ(\({\textsf{T}}\), A). In the second section it is proved that the deontic system KD is translationally equivalent to an axiomatic system of dyadic noncontingency named KDΔ2, and that the minimal system KΔ of monadic contingency is a fragment of KDΔ2. The last section suggests lines for further inquiries.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
¥17,985 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (Japan)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. By “direct definition” we intend here simply that the definiens involves a wff containing only one operator, while (Def □) contains beyond ∇ also ¬.

  2. Pelletier and Urquhart (2003), p. 263.

  3. Pelletier and Urquhart (2003), p. 268.

  4. In fact, as the authors write: “Since we have assumed that the rule of detachment holds for the biconditional in the two systems, these conditions ensure that both t1 and t2 are exact. This can be seen as follows. If At1 is provable in \({\mathcal{S}}2\), then \(({\mathsf{At}}_{1} )t_{2}\) is provable in \({\mathcal{S}}1\); but then, since \(({\mathsf{At}}_{1} )t_{2} \equiv A\) is a theorem of \({\mathcal{S}}1\), A must also be a theorem of \({\mathcal{S}}1\)” (p. 268).

  5. The author wishes to thank the anonymous referee for the careful reading of the paper and for the suggested improvements.

References

  • Cresswell, M. J. (1988). Necessity and contingency. Studia Logica, 47, 145–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fan, J., Wang, Y., & van Ditmarsch, H. (2014). Almost necessary. In R. Goré, B. Kooi, & A. Kurucz (Eds.), Advances in modal logic (Vol. 10, pp. 178–196). World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone, L. (1995). The logic of noncontingency. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 36, 214–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone, L. (2002). The modal logic of agreement and noncontingency. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 43, 95–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone, L. (2013). Zolin and Pizzi: Defining necessity from noncontingency. Erkenntnis, 78, 1275–1302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, S. (1995). Minimal noncontingency logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 36, 230–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pelletier, F. J., & Urquhart, A. (2003). Synonymous logics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 32, 259–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pizzi, C. (1999). Contingency logics and propositional quantification. Manuscrito (UNICAMP, Campinas University) (Vol. 22, pp. 283–303).

  • Pizzi, C. (2007). Necessity and relative contingency. Studia Logica, 85, 395–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zolin, E. (1999). Completeness and definability in the logic of noncontingency. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 40, 533–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Claudio E. A. Pizzi.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

T1. Let L be is a normal modal logic extended with the definition Δ(A, B) = df(A ⊃ B) ∨ (A ⊃ ¬B). Suppose that among the frames for L there is a frame containing some worlds with no R-successors and a frame containing a world with exactly one R-successor. Then □ is not definable in terms of Δ.

Proof

Let us consider the disjoint union of two such frames, since the exposed condition is equivalent to requiring that there is a frame for the logic L containing both a world with no successors and a world with exactly one successor, however many additional worlds are related. For simplicity we will assume the worlds w0, w1 come from a single frame, wi having i worlds R-related to it (i = 0; 1). This means that wi is either and end-point or there is only one world wj s.t. wiRwj. Construct a model M on this frame by having w0 verify the same propositional variables as w1. For the present purposes a convenient choice will be to stipulate, for each pj and each wi, that V(pj, wi) = 0, i.e. that each variable pj is false at every world of M. Then by induction on the construction of C, it turns out that all formulas C whose form is ¬A, A ∧ B, have value 1 at all the worlds of M, or value 0 at all of them. As far as Δ- formulas are concerned, since Δ(A, B) is equivalent to □(A ⊃ B) ∨ □(A ⊃ ¬B), it is straightforward to see that all such formulas have value 1 at w0 and w1 in M or in any other model on the same frame (since it takes two R-successors to falsify such a formula). To sum up, for every wff C containing the connectives ¬, ∧, Δ we are able to prove that V(C, w0) = V(C, w1). But this property does not hold for □-formulas. In fact, since w0 is a dead end, we have in M that V(□p1, w0) = 1; but V(□p1, w1) = 0 since there is a wj s.t. w1Rwj and p1 has value 0 at wj. Thus no formula constructed using the Boolean connectives and Δ can be provably equivalent in L to □p1. ■

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pizzi, C.E.A. Possibility and Dyadic Contingency. J of Log Lang and Inf 31, 451–463 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-022-09352-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-022-09352-3

Keywords

Navigation