Abstract
We analyze lobbying as contest in which lobbyists exert effort to pull a policy outcome in a multidimensional space in their preferred directions. We prove existence and uniqueness of equilibrium and perform comparative statics on the cost of effort and policy utility of the lobbyists. As cost of effort increases, the equilibrium policy outcome and inefficiency (i.e., total effort expended) are constant. Assuming power utility, the equilibrium policy minimizes a social loss function that depends on curvature of utilities. As lobbyists become less tolerant of larger losses, the equilibrium policy outcome converges to the Rawlsian policy, which maximizes the payoff of the worst-off lobbyist, and inefficiency may become large or go to zero, depending on the configuration of ideal points. As lobbyists become less tolerant of smaller losses, the equilibrium outcome converges to the mean of the lobbyists’ ideal points, and inefficiency goes to zero.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
Intuitively, if output is highly homogeneous, as would be the case in agricultural markets, then foreign products priced to slightly undercut the domestic market will lead to a sharp decrease in profits of domestic firms. In the opposite case where outputs are very distinct, e.g., if consumer brand loyalty is strong, then failure to obtain desired import restrictions would entail a smaller decrease in profits.
Chung and Duggan (2018) extend the concept of geometric median to non-Euclidean utilities, and they motivate their concept of directional equilibrium as a tug of war; in contrast to the current paper, it is implicitly assumed that all voters pull with equal force. See the literature review of that paper for a history of the geometric median idea.
References
Banks J (2000) Buying supermajorities in finite legislatures. Am Political Sci Rev 94:677–681
Banks J, Duggan J (2000) A bargaining model of collective choice. Am Political Sci Rev 94:73–88
Banks J, Duggan J (2006) A general bargaining model of legislative policy-making. Q J Political Sci 1:49–85
Baron D, Ferejohn J (1989) Bargaining in legislatures. Am Political Sci Rev 83:1181–1206
Baye M, Kovenock D, De Vries C (1993) Rigging the lobbying process: an application of the all-pay auction. Am Econ Rev 83:289–294
Baye M, Kovenock D, De Vries C (1996) The all-pay auction with complete information. Econ Theory 8:291–305
Bernheim D, Whinston M (1986a) Menu auctions, resource allocation, and economic influence. Q J Political Sci 101:1–31
Bernheim D, Whinston M (1986b) Common agency. Econometrica 54:923–942
Che Y-K, Gale I (1998) Caps on political lobbying. Am Econ Rev 88:643–651
Chung H, Duggan J (2018) Directional equilibria. J Theor Politics 30:272–305
Corchón L (2007) The theory of contests: a survey. Rev Econ Des 11:69–100
Dekel E, Jackson M, Wolinsky A (2008) Vote buying: legislatures and lobbying. Q J Polit Sci 4:103–128
Epstein G, Nitzan S (2004) Strategic restraint in contests. Eur Econ Rev 48:201–210
Esteban J, Ray D (1999) Conflict and distribution. J Econ Theory 87:379–415
Groseclose T, Snyder J (1996) Buying supermajorities. Am Political Sci Rev 90:303–315
Grossman G, Helpman E (1994) Protection for sale. Am Econ Rev 84:833–850
Hillman A, Riley J (1989) Politically contestable rents and transfers. Econ Politics 1:17–39
Konrad K (2000) Spatial contests. Int J Ind Organ 18:965–974
Konrad K, Kovenock D (2005) Equilibrium and efficiency in the tug-of-war. CESifo Working Paper No. 1562
Laussel D, Le Breton M (2001) Conflict and cooperation: the structure of equilibrium payoffs in common agency. J Econ Theory 100:93–128
Le Breton M, Salanié F (2003) Lobbying under political uncertainty. J Public Econ 87:2589–2610
Linster B (1993) Stackelberg rent-seeking. Public Choice 77:307–321
Martimort D, Semenov A (2008) Ideological uncertainty and lobbying competition. J Public Econ 92:456–481
Mitra D (1999) Endogenous lobby formation and endogenous protection: a long-run model of trade policy determination. Am Econ Rev 89:1116–1134
Münster J (2006) Lobbying contests with endogenous policy proposals. Econ Politics 18:389–397
Plott C (1967) A notion of equilibrium and its possibility under majority rule. Am Econ Rev 57:787–806
Reny P (1999) On the existence of pure and mixed strategy nash equilibria in discontinuous games. Econometrica 67:1029–1056
Skaperdas S (1996) Contest success functions. Econ Theory 7:283–290
Tullock G (1980) Efficient rent seeking. In: Buchanen J, Tollison R, Tullock G (eds) Toward a theory of the rent-seeking society. Texas A & M University Press, College Station, pp 97–112
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
We thank Dan Kovenock for valuable comments on our paper.
A Proofs of propositions
A Proofs of propositions
Proof of Proposition 1:
We verify (A2) and (A3). For the former, it suffices to show that the second derivative of \(u(\Vert x^{*}-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert )-c\alpha _{i}^{2}\) with respect to \(\alpha _{i}\) is negative. For any lobbyist i, the first derivative with respect to \(\alpha _{i}\) is the following:
The second derivative simplifies to:
as required. To verify (A3), write
as required. \(\square \)
Proof of Proposition 2:
Suppose toward a contradiction that there exist distinct policies \(x'\) and \(x''\) such that \( \min _{i} f_{i}(x') = \min _{i} f_{i}(x'') = \max _{x} \min _{i} f_{i}(x)\), and let \(\underline{u}\) denote this value. Set \(x''' = \frac{1}{2}x' + \frac{1}{2}x''\), and let k solve \(\min _{i} f(x''')\), so that \(f_{k}\) is among the functions taking the lowest value at \(x'''\). By construction, we have
Then strict quasi-concavity implies \(f_{k}(x''') > \underline{u}\), but this implies that \(x'\) and \(x''\) do not solve \(\max _{x}\min _{i}f_{i}(x)\), a contradiction. We conclude that the latter problem has a unique solution, as required. \(\square \)
Proof of Proposition 3:
First, assume \(x=x^{R}\), and suppose toward a contradiction that x is not a convex combination of ideal points of lobbyists belonging to N(x). Then x is not Pareto optimal for the lobbyists in this set, and there exists \(x'\) such that for all \(i \in N(x)\), we have \(u(\Vert x'-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert ) > u(\Vert x-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert )\). For each \(\epsilon \in (0,1)\), define \(x^{\epsilon }=(1-\epsilon )x + \epsilon x'\), and note that strict quasi-concavity implies that for all such \(\epsilon \) and all \(i \in N(x)\), we have \(u(\Vert x^{\epsilon }-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert ) > u(\Vert x-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert )\). Furthermore, by continuity of u, we can choose \(\epsilon >0\) sufficiently small that for all \(i \in N \setminus N(x)\), we have \(u(\Vert x^{\epsilon }-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert ) > u(\Vert x-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert )\). But then we have
a contradiction. We conclude that x is a convex combination of ideal points of lobbyists in N(x).
For the converse, assume that x is a convex combination of ideal points of lobbyists in N(x), and suppose toward a contradiction that \(x \ne x^{R}\). Then we have
Since \(x^{R} \ne x\) and \(x \in \text{ conv }\{\hat{x}^{i} \mid i \in N(x)\}\), it follows that if \(\Vert \hat{x}^{i}-x^{R}\Vert < \Vert \hat{x}^{i}-x\Vert \) for some \(i \in N(x)\), then there is some \(k \in N(x)\) such that \(\Vert \hat{x}^{k}-x\Vert < \Vert \hat{x}^{k}-x^{R}\Vert \). But this would imply
a contradiction. Thus, we must have \(u(\Vert x-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert ) = u(\Vert x^{R}-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert )\) for all \(i \in N(x)\). For each \(\epsilon \in (0,1)\), define \(x^{\epsilon }=(1-\epsilon )x+\epsilon x^{R}\), and note that strict quasi-concavity implies that for all such \(\epsilon \) and all \(i \in N(x)\), we have \(u(\Vert x^{\epsilon }-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert ) > u(\Vert x^{R}-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert )\). Furthermore, by continuity of u, we can choose \(\epsilon >0\) sufficiently small that for all \(i \in N \setminus N(x)\), we have \(u(\Vert x^{\epsilon }-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert ) > u(\Vert x^{R}-\hat{x}^{i}\Vert )\), which leads to a contradiction, as above. We conclude that \(x=x^{R}\), as required. \(\square \)
Proof of Proposition 4:
Suppose otherwise, toward a contradiction. By Theorem 1, there is a unique equilibrium outcome \(x^{*}\), and this is characterized as the unique solution to (3). By exact radial symmetry, there is a bijective mapping \(\phi :N \rightarrow N\) such that for each lobbyist i, we have \(\hat{x}^{i} - x = x- \hat{x}^{\phi (i)}\), i.e., the ideal point of lobbyist i coincides with the reflection of the ideal point of lobbyist \(\phi (i)\) through x. Since \(\phi \) is bijective, we can rewrite (3), by a change of variables and multiplying by negative one, as
Using \(\hat{x}^{\phi (i)}=2x-\hat{x}^{i}\), we write this as
We conclude that the policy \(2x-x^{*} \ne x^{*}\) satisfies (3), as does \(x^{*}\), contradicting the fact that the system has a unique solution. \(\square \)
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Duggan, J., Gao, J. Lobbying as a multidimensional tug of war. Soc Choice Welf 54, 141–166 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-019-01215-4
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-019-01215-4