Consistency and the core in games with externalities | International Journal of Game Theory
Skip to main content

Consistency and the core in games with externalities

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
International Journal of Game Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the presence of externalities across coalitions, Dutta et al. (J Econ Theory 145:2380–2411, 2010) characterize their value by extending Hart and Mas-Colell reduced game consistency. In the present paper, we provide a characterization result for the core for games with externalities by extending one form of consistency studied by Moulin (J Econ Theory 36:120–148, 1985), which is often referred to as the complement-reduced game property. Moreover, we analyze another consistency formulated by Davis and Maschler (Naval Res Logist Quart 12:223–259, 1965), called the max-reduced game property and a final consistency called the projection-reduced game property. In environments with externalities, we discuss some asymmetric results among these different forms of reduced games.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
¥17,985 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (Japan)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Formally, for any partition \(\mathcal {P}\) and coalition \(S\subseteq N\), let \(\mathcal {P}|_S\) be given by \(\mathcal {P}|_S=\{S \cap C\ |\ C\in \mathcal {P},\ S\cap C\ne \emptyset \}\in \varPi (S)\).

  2. The terminology of the m-core and the s-core is introduced by Hafalir (2007).

  3. Abe and Funaki (2016) generalize the Bondareva-Shapley condition and define the class \(\varGamma _{C^{\psi }}\). The balancedness of each type of core is also studied.

  4. Formally, as in Lemma 1, we have \((v^{-i_1}_{m1})^{-i_2}_{m1}=(v^{-i_2}_{m1})^{-i_1}_{m1}\). However, there possibly exist partitions \(\mathcal {P}\) and \(\mathcal {P'}\) such that \(v^{N{\setminus } \{i_1,i_2\},\mathcal {P}, x}_{m1}\ne v^{N{\setminus } \{i_1,i_2\},\mathcal {P'}, x}_{m1}\), where (m1) can be replaced with (m2) or (p).

References

  • Abe T, Funaki Y (2016) The non-emptiness of the core of a partition function form game. Int J Game Theory (forthcoming)

  • Albizuri MJ, Arin J, Rubio J (2005) An axiom system for a value for games in partition function form. Int Game Theory Rev 7:63–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloch F (1996) Sequential formation of coalitions in games with externalities and fixed payoff division. Games Econ Behav 14:90–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloch F, van den Nouweland A (2014) Expectation formation rules and the core of partition function games. Games Econ Behav 88:339–353

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolger E (1989) A set of axioms for a value for partition function games. Int J Game Theory 18:37–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis M, Maschler M (1965) The kernel of a cooperative game. Naval Res Logist Quart 12:223–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta B, Ehlers L, Kar A (2010) Externalities, potential, value and consistency. J Econ Theory 145:2380–2411

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Funaki Y, Yamato T (2001) The core and consistency properties: a general characterization. Int Game Theory Rev 3:175–187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg J (1994) Coalition structures. Handbook of game theory with economic applications, Chapter 37. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Hafalir IE (2007) Efficiency in coalition games with externalities. Games Econ Behav 61:242–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart S, Kurz M (1983) Endogenous formation of coalitions. Econometrica 51:1047–1064

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kóczy L (2007) A recursive core for partition function form games. Theory Decis 63:41–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kóczy L, Lauwers L (2004) The coalition structure core is accessible. Games Econ Behav 48:86–93

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macho-Stadler I, Pérez-Castrillo D, Wettstein D (2007) Sharing the surplus: an extension of the Shapley value for environments with externalities. J Econ Theory 135:339–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin H (1985) The separability axiom and equal-sharing methods. J Econ Theory 36:120–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson R (1977) Values of games in partition function form. Int J Game Theory 6:23–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peleg B (1986) On the reduced game property and its converse. Int J Game Theory 15:187–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tadenuma K (1992) Reduced games, consistency, and the core. Int J Game Theory 20:325–334

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Takaaki Abe.

Additional information

The author is grateful to two anonymous referees for their helpful suggestions and comments. The author also thanks Yukihiko Funaki for helpful conversations. The author acknowledges the financial support from Japan Society for Promotion of Science (JSPS).

Appendix

Appendix

To distinguish each form of reduced game, in this appendix, we use symbols \(v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{m1}\), \(v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{m2}\), \(v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{p}\) and \(v^{S,x}_{c}\) to denote max(I), max(II), projection and complement-type of reduced game, respectively. Tables 3 and 4 correspond to Tables 1 and 2, respectively. The number assigned to each cell represents the proposition or example describing the cell, e.g., for the proposition showing that the optimistic core satisfies Max-I RGP, see Proposition 5.

Table 3 The relationship between expectation cores and RGP (corresponding to Table 1)
Table 4 The relationship between expectation functions and consistency (corresponding to Table 2)

Proposition 3

If \(\psi \) is optimistic or pessimistic, then \(\psi \) is CC.

Proof

We denote by \(\psi ^{opt}\) the optimistic expectation function. Let (Nv) be a game, and \(S\subseteq N\) (\(|S|\ge 2\)). We define \(\mathcal {P}^*\) as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} \mathcal {P}^*:= \psi ^{opt}(N,v,S)=\mathop {\mathrm{arg~max}}\limits _{\mathcal {P'} \in \varPi (N{\setminus } S)} v(S,\mathcal {P'}). \end{aligned}$$
(9)

For any \(h\in S\) and \(x\in \mathbb {R}^N\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} v^{N{\setminus } h,x}_{c}(S{\setminus } h,\mathcal {P}^*)= & {} v(S,\mathcal {P}^*)-x_h\\= & {} \max _{\mathcal {P'} \in \varPi (N{\setminus } S)}[v(S,\mathcal {P'})-x_h]\\= & {} \max _{\mathcal {P'} \in \varPi (N{\setminus } S)}[v^{N{\setminus } h,x}_{c}(S{\setminus } h,\mathcal {P'})], \end{aligned}$$

where the first equality holds by the definition of complement reduced games, the second by (9) and the last by the definition of complement reduced games. Hence, we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \mathcal {P}^*=\mathop {\mathrm{arg~max}}\limits _{\mathcal {P'} \in \varPi (N{\setminus } S)} v^{N{\setminus } h,x}_{c}(S{\setminus } h,\mathcal {P'}) = \psi ^{opt}(N{\setminus } h,v^{N{\setminus } h,x}_{c},S{\setminus } h), \end{aligned}$$

and, then, \(\psi ^{opt}(N,v,S)=\psi ^{opt}(N{\setminus } h,v^{N{\setminus } h,x}_{c},S{\setminus } h)\), which implies \(\psi ^{opt}\) is CC.

By replacing \(\max \) with \(\min \), we complete the proof of the pessimistic expectation function \(\psi ^{pes}\) as well. \(\square \)

Proposition 4

If \(\psi \) satisfies the following condition: for any games (Nv), (Mw), and nonempty coalitions \(S\subseteq N\), \(T\subseteq M\),

$$\begin{aligned} N{\setminus } S = M{\setminus } T \Longrightarrow \psi (N,v,S) = \psi (M,w,T), \end{aligned}$$
(10)

then \(\psi \) satisfies all four types of consistencies: Max-I, Max-II, Projection and Complement.

Proof

We prove CC (or, complement consistency). The other types of consistencies are obtained in the same way. Fix a game (Nv). For any \(x\in \mathbb {R}^N\) and \(h\in N\), we can specify the complement reduced game \((N{\setminus } h,v^{N{\setminus } h,x}_{c})\). For any S such that \(h\in S \subseteq N\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} N{\setminus } S = (N{\setminus } h){\setminus }(S{\setminus } h). \end{aligned}$$

Using (10), we obtain \(\psi (N,v,S) = \psi (N{\setminus } h,v^{N{\setminus } h,x}_{c},S{\setminus } h,)\) \(\square \)

Lemma 4

If \(\psi \) is the singleton-expectation, then \(\psi \) satisfies (10).

Proof

We denote by \(\psi ^{s}\) the singleton-expectation function. For any nonempty T and S with \(T\in S\subseteq N\), and any \(w:EC(N{\setminus } T)\rightarrow \mathbb {R}\), we have \(\psi ^{s}(N,v,S)=\{\{i\}|i \in N{\setminus } S\}=\psi ^{s}(N{\setminus } T,w,S{\setminus } T)\). \(\square \)

Lemma 5

If \(\psi \) is the merge-expectation, then \(\psi \) satisfies (10).

Proof

This is similar to Lemma 4. Let \(\psi ^{m}\) denote the merge-expectation function. We have \(\psi ^{m}(N,v,S)=\{N{\setminus } S\}=\psi ^{m}(N{\setminus } T,w,S{\setminus } T)\). \(\square \)

Corollary 2

If \(\psi \) is the singleton-expectation or the merge-expectation, then \(\psi \) satisfies all four types of consistencies.

Proof

See Lemmas 4, 5 and Proposition 4. \(\square \)

Example 3

Consider the following 4-player game: \(N=\{i_1,i_2,i_3,i_4\}\);

$$\begin{aligned}&v(N,\{\emptyset \})=12;\\&v(\{i,j,k\}, \left\{ \{h\}\right\} )=5\ and\ v(\{h\}, \left\{ \{i,j,k\}\right\} )=0,\ \ for\ \{i,j,k,h\}=N;\\&v(\{i,j\}, \left\{ \{k,h\}\right\} )=4,\ \ for\ \{i,j,k,h\}=N;\\&v(\{i,j\}, \left\{ \{k\},\{h\}\right\} )=3\ and\ v(\{k\}, \left\{ \{i,j\},\{h\}\right\} )=1,\ \ for\ \{i,j,k,h\}=N;\\&v(\{i\}, \left\{ \{j\},\{k\},\{h\}\right\} )=2,\ \ for\ \{i,j,k,h\}=N. \end{aligned}$$

Let \(x=(3,3,3,3)\), \(S=\{i_1,i_2\}\) and player \(h=1\). For the optimistic expectation function, we have

$$\begin{aligned} \mathop {\mathrm{arg~max}}\limits _{\mathcal {P}'\in \varPi (N{\setminus } S)}v(S,\mathcal {P}')= \{\{i_3,i_4\}\}, \end{aligned}$$

because \(\max _{\mathcal {P}'\in \varPi (N{\setminus } S)}v(S,\mathcal {P}')\!\!=\!\max \{v(S, \{\{i_3,i_4\}\}), v(S,\{\{i_3\},\{i_4\}\})\}\!=\!\!\max \{4, 3 \}\). However, in the Max-I reduced game, we have

$$\begin{aligned} \mathop {\mathrm{arg~max}}\limits _{\mathcal {P}'\in \varPi (N{\setminus } S)}v^{-h}_{m1}(S{\setminus } h,\mathcal {P}')= \{\{i_3\},\{i_4\}\}, \end{aligned}$$

because

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{\mathcal {P}'\in \varPi (N{\setminus } S)}v^{-h}_{m1}(S{\setminus } h,\mathcal {P}')= & {} \max \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} v(S, \{\{i_3,i_4\}\})-x_h,&{} v(S{\setminus } h, \{\{i_1\},\{i_3,i_4\}\}),\\ v(S,\{\{i_3\},\{i_4\}\})-x_h,&{} v(S{\setminus } h, \{\{i_1\},\{i_3\},\{i_4\}\}) \end{array} \right\} \nonumber \\= & {} \max \{4-3 ,1, 3-3, 2\}\nonumber \\= & {} 2, \end{aligned}$$
(11)

which is the worth of the bottom-right element in (11). Hence, \(\psi ^{opt}(N,v,S)=\{\{i_3,i_4\}\} \ne \{\{i_3\},\{i_4\}\}=\psi ^{opt}(N{\setminus } h,v^{-h}_{m1},S{\setminus } h)\). For the optimistic expectation function, this example is still valid for Max-II and Projection consistencies as well. For the pessimistic expectation function, we can generate the example by swapping \(v(\{i,j\}, \left\{ \{i,j\},\{k,h\}\right\} )\) for \(v(\{i,j\}, \left\{ \{i,j\},\{k\},\{h\}\right\} )\).

Lemma 6

Let \((N,v)\in \varGamma \). Let \(S\subseteq N\), \(\mathcal {P}\in \varPi (N{\setminus } S)\) and \(x\in \mathbb {R}^N\). We denote each type of reduced game by \(v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{m1}\), \(v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{m2}\), \(v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{p}\) and \(v^{S,x}_{c}\), respectively. Then, for any \(T\subseteq S\) \((T\ne \emptyset )\) and \(\mathcal {Q}\in \varPi (S{\setminus } T)\), we have

$$\begin{aligned}&v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{m1}(T,\mathcal {Q})\ge v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{m2}(T,\mathcal {Q}),\\&v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{m2}(T,\mathcal {Q})\ge v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{p}(T,\mathcal {Q}),\\&v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{m2}(T,\mathcal {Q})\ge v^{S,x}_{c}(T,\mathcal {Q}). \end{aligned}$$

Proof

The first inequality follows from the domain of maximization: in view of the definitions, for any \(\mathcal {P}\in \varPi (N{\setminus } S)\),

$$\begin{aligned} \{C|C\in \mathcal {P}\} \text { (or, Max-II) } \subseteq \{C|C\subseteq N{\setminus } S\} \text { (or, Max-I) }. \end{aligned}$$

The second (third) inequality holds because we can take \(\emptyset \) (\(N{\setminus } S\)) as maximizer C. \(\square \)

Proposition 5

The optimistic-core satisfies all types of RGP on \(\varGamma _{C^{opt}}\): maxI-RGP, maxII-RGP, projection-RGP and comp-RGP.

Proof

Let \(C^{opt}(N,v)\) be the optimistic core of (Nv) and \(x\in C^{opt}(N,v)\). We show that the optimistic-core satisfies maxI-RGP. For any \(S\subseteq N\), \(T\subsetneq S\) \((T\ne \emptyset )\) and \(\mathcal {P}\in \varPi (N{\setminus } S)\), we have

$$\begin{aligned}&\sum _{j\in T}x_j - \max _{\mathcal {Q}\in \varPi (S{\setminus } T)} v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{m1}(T,\mathcal {Q}) \nonumber \\&\quad =\sum _{j\in T}x_j - \max _{\mathcal {Q}\in \varPi (S{\setminus } T)} \max _{C\subseteq N{\setminus } S}\left[ v(T\cup C, \mathcal {Q} \cup (\mathcal {P}|_{(N{\setminus } S){\setminus } C})) - \sum _{j\in C}x_j \right] \nonumber \\&\quad =\sum _{j\in T}x_j - \left[ v(T\cup C^*, \mathcal {Q}^* \cup (\mathcal {P}|_{(N{\setminus } S){\setminus } C^*})) - \sum _{j\in C^*}x_j\right] \end{aligned}$$
(12)
$$\begin{aligned}&\quad =\sum _{j\in T\cup C^*}x_j - v(T\cup C^*, \mathcal {Q}^* \cup (\mathcal {P}|_{(N{\setminus } S){\setminus } C^*})) \nonumber \\&\quad \ge \max _{\mathcal {P'}\in \varPi (N{\setminus } (T\cup C^*))} \ v(T\cup C^*,\mathcal {P'})- v(T\cup C^*, \mathcal {Q}^* \cup (\mathcal {P}|_{(N{\setminus } S){\setminus } C^*})) \nonumber \\&\quad \ge 0, \end{aligned}$$
(13)

where \(C^*,\mathcal {Q}^*\) in (12) are maximizers of the target formula, and (13) holds because \(x\in C^{opt}(N,v)\). Similarly, for \(T=S\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j\in S}x_j-v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}(S,\{\emptyset \})= & {} \sum _{j\in S}x_j-\left( v(N,\{\emptyset \})-\sum _{j\in N{\setminus } S}x_j \right) \\= & {} \sum _{j\in N}x_j-v(N,\{\emptyset \})\\= & {} 0. \end{aligned}$$

By Lemma 6, we can replace \(v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{m1}\) with \(v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{m2}\), \(v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{p}\) and \(v^{S,\mathcal {P},x}_{c}\), respectively. Then, we obtain the desired proposition. \(\square \)

Example 4

Consider the following 4-player game: \(N=\{1,2,3,4\}\),

$$\begin{aligned} v(S,\mathcal {P})= \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 12 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(N,\{\emptyset \}),\\ 6 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(\{i,j\},\{\{k\},\{h\}\}),\\ 0 &{} \text {otherwise.} \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

Let \(x=(x_1,x_2,x_3,x_4)=(1,3,4,4)\). Then, \(x\in C^{pes}(N,v)=C^{m}(N,v)\). Now, for \(S=\{1,2\}\) and \(\mathcal {P}=\{\{3\},\{4\}\}\), we have the following Max-I reduced game:

$$\begin{aligned}&v^{S,P,x}_{m1}(\{1,2\},\{\emptyset \})= 12-(4+4)=4,\\&v^{S,P,x}_{m1}(\{1\},\{\{2\}\})= 6-4=2,\\&v^{S,P,x}_{m1}(\{2\},\{\{1\}\})= 6-4=2. \end{aligned}$$

The restriction of x, \(x_S=(1,3)\), is out of the pessimistic core (and the m-core) of the reduced game: \(x_S=(1,3)\not \in \{(2,2)\}=C^{pes}(S,v^{S,P,x}_{m1})=C^{m}(S,v^{S,P,x}_{m1})\). We have the Max-II reduced game as well as Max-I.

Example 5

Consider the following 5-player game: \(N=\{1,2,3,4,5\}\),

$$\begin{aligned} v(S,\mathcal {P})= \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 15 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(N,\{\emptyset \}),\\ 7 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(\{i,j\},\{\{k\},\{h,l\}\}),\\ 0 &{} \text {otherwise.} \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

Let \(x=(x_1,x_2,x_3,x_4,x_5)=(2,2,4,4,3)\). Then, \(x\in C^{s}(N,v)\). For \(S=\{3,4\}\) (who obtain 4 in x) and \(\mathcal {P}=\{\{1\},\{2,5\}\}\), we have the following Max-I reduced game:

$$\begin{aligned}&v^{S,P,x}_{m1}(\{3,4\},\{\emptyset \})= 15-(2+2+3)=8,\\&v^{S,P,x}_{m1}(\{3\},\{\{4\}\})= 7-2=5,\\&v^{S,P,x}_{m1}(\{4\},\{\{3\}\})= 7-2=5. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, the s-core is empty. We have the same result in Max-II as well as Max-I.

Example 6

Consider the following 4-player game: \(N=\{1,2,3,4\}\),

$$\begin{aligned} v(S,\mathcal {P})= \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 12 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(N,\{\emptyset \}),\\ 4 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(\{i\},\{\{j,k,h\}\}),\\ 4 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(\{i\},\{\{j,k\},\{h\}\}),\\ 3 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(\{i\},\{\{j\},\{k\},\{h\}\}),\\ 0 &{} \text {otherwise.} \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

Let \(x=(x_1,x_2,x_3,x_4)=(3,3,3,3)\). Then, \(x\in C^{pes}(N,v)=C^{s}(N,v)\). For \(S=\{1,2\}\) and \(\mathcal {P}=\{\{3,4\}\}\), we have the following projection reduced game:

$$\begin{aligned}&v^{S,P,x}_{p}(\{1,2\},\{\emptyset \})= 12-(3+3)=6,\\&v^{S,P,x}_{p}(\{1\},\{\{2\}\})= 4,\\&v^{S,P,x}_{p}(\{2\},\{\{1\}\})=4. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, the pessimistic core and the s-core are empty in the reduced game.

Example 7

Consider the following 4-player game: \(N=\{1,2,3,4\}\),

$$\begin{aligned} v(S,\mathcal {P})= \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 12 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(N,\{\emptyset \}),\\ 3 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(\{i\},\{\{j,k,h\}\}),\\ 4 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(\{i\},\{\{j,k\},\{h\}\}),\\ 4 &{} \text {if }(S,\mathcal {P})=(\{i\},\{\{j\},\{k\},\{h\}\}),\\ 0 &{} \text {otherwise.} \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

Let \(x=(x_1,x_2,x_3,x_4)=(3,3,3,3)\). Then, \(x\in C^{m}(N,v)\). For \(S=\{1,2\}\) and \(\mathcal {P}=\{\{3,4\}\}\), we have the following projection reduced game:

$$\begin{aligned}&v^{S,P,x}_{p}(\{1,2\},\{\emptyset \})= 12-(3+3)=6,\\&v^{S,P,x}_{p}(\{1\},\{\{2\}\})= 4,\\&v^{S,P,x}_{p}(\{2\},\{\{1\}\})=4. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, the m-core of the reduced game becomes empty.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Abe, T. Consistency and the core in games with externalities. Int J Game Theory 47, 133–154 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-017-0581-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-017-0581-y

Keywords