Abstract
The control principle implies that people should not feel guilt for outcomes beyond their control. Yet, the so-called ‘agent and observer puzzles’ in philosophy demonstrate that people waver in their commitment to the control principle when reflecting on accidental outcomes. In the context of car accidents involving conventional or autonomous vehicles (AVs), Study 1 established that judgments of responsibility are most strongly associated with expressions of guilt–over and above other negative emotions, such as sadness, remorse or anger. Studies 2 and 3 then confirmed that, while people generally endorse the control principle, and deny that occupants in an AV should feel guilt when involved in an accident, they nevertheless ascribe guilt to those same occupants. Study 3 also uncovered novel implications of the observer puzzle in the legal context: Passengers in an AV were seen as more legally liable than either passengers in a conventional vehicle, or even their drivers–especially when participants were prompted to reflect on the passengers’ affective experience of guilt. Our findings document an important conflict–in the context of AV accidents–between people’s prescriptive reasoning about responsibility and guilt on one hand, and their counter-normative experience of guilt on the other, with apparent implications for liability decisions.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
A fully autonomous vehicle has been defined by the United States of America’s National Highway Traffic Safety Administration (NHTSA 2016) as the following: “The vehicle is designed to perform all safety–critical driving functions and monitor roadway conditions for an entire trip. Such a design anticipates that the driver will provide destination or navigation input but is not expected to be available for control at any time during the trip. This includes both occupied and unoccupied vehicles. By design, safe operation rests solely on the automated vehicle system”. (NHTSA,2016).
It seems that Mercedes-Benz intended to advertise its AV by ensuring that they would prioritize the occupant’s life above all: “Car and Driver reported on October 7 that Mercedes-Benz has already made a decision that its self-driving cars will always prioritize their own occupants over other road users. The automaker said it was wrong — and possibly illegal” (https://www.businessinsider.com/mercedes-denies-claim-its-driverless-car-will-prioritize-driver-safety-2016-10?IR=T, retrieved March 2, 2020).
That the guilt feeling is appropriate does not mean that it is rational (as advocated by Sussman 2018), nor does it mean that it is irrational, as the logic of appropriateness is not necessarily linked to the logic of consequences (Balsige, 2014), which should be understood in this context as the (necessary) connection between the principle of control and the guilt feeling.
The Ethics Committee of the Spanish Council for Scientific Research (CSIC) has favorably evaluated this research (Committee Internal Code: 113/2020).
“AAA’s [American Automobile Association] annual automated vehicle survey found that 71 percent of people are afraid to ride in fully self-driving vehicles” (Edmons, E., 2019). See also Zhigang et al., 2018.
References
Awad, E., Dsouza, S., Kim, R., Schultz, J., Henrich, J., Shariff, A., Bonnefon, J.-F., & Rahwan, I. (2018). The moral machine experiment. Nature, 563, 59–64.
Awad, E., Levine, S., Kleiman-Weiner, M., Dsouza, S., Tenenbaum, J. B., Shariff, A., Bonnefon, J.-F., & Rahwan, I. (2020). Drivers are blamed more than their automated cars when both make mistakes. Nature Human Behaviour, 4(2), 134–143.
Balsiger, J. (2014). Logic of appropriateness. Encyclopedia Britannica. Available at http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/1937900/logic-ofappropriateness. Retrieved May 12, 2021.
Baumeister, R., Stillwell, A., & Heatherton, T. (1994). Guilt: An interpersonal approach. Psychological Bulletin, 115(2), 243–267.
Bennet, R., Vijaygopal, R., & Kottasz, R. (2020). Willingness of people who are blind to accept autonomous vehicles: An empirical investigation. Transportation Research Part f: Traffic Psychology and Behaviour, 69, 13–27.
Bieker, S. (2012). Legal aspects of autonomous driving. Santa Clara Law Review, 52, 1146–1156.
Bissel, D., Birtchnell, T., Elliott, A., & Hsu, E. L. (2018). Autonomous automobilities: The social impact of driverless vehicles. Current Sociology, 68, 116–134.
Bonnefon, J.-F., Shariff, A., & Rahwan, I. (2016). The social dilemma of autonomous vehicles. Science, 352, 1573–1576.
Campos, A. S. (2013). Responsibility and justice in aristotle’s non-voluntary and mixed actions. Journal of Ancient Philosophy, 7, 100–121.
Carlsson, A. B. (2017). Blameworthiness as deserved guilt. Journal of Ethics, 21, 89–115.
Coeckelbergh, M. (2020). AI Ethics, Mit Press.
Cordner, C. (2007). Guilt, remorse and victims. Philosophical Investigations, 30, 337–362.
De Rivera, J. (1984). The structure of emotional relationships. Review of Personality & Social Psychology.
Deem, M. J., & Ramsey, G. (2016). Guilt by association? Philosophical Psychology, 4, 570–585.
Edmons, E. (2019). Self-driving vehicles. https://newsroom.aaa.com/2019/03/americans-fear-self-driving-cars-survey/. Retrieved 5 July, 2021.
Enoch, D. (2012). Being responsible, taking responsibility, and penumbral agency. In U. Heuer & G. Lang (Ed.), Luck, value, and commitment: Themes from the ethics of Bernard Williams. Oxford University Press.
Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge University Press
Gill, T. (2020). Blame it on the self-driving car: How autonomous vehicles can alter consumer morality. Journal of Consumer Research, 47(2), 272–291.
Gill, T. (2021). Ethical dilemmas are really important to potential adopters of autonomous vehicles. Ethics and Information Technology. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-021-09605-y
Greenspan, P. S. (1992). Subjective guilt and responsibility. Mind, 101, 287–303.
Gregory, A. (2017). The sorrow and the shame of the accidental killer. The New Yorker, September 18.
Heuer, U. & Lang, G. (Eds.) (2011). Luck, value, and commitment - Themes from the ethics of Bernard Williams. Oxford University Press.
Hieronymi, P. (2004). The force and fairness of blame. Philosophical Perspectives, 18, 115–148.
Himmelreich, J. (2028). Never mind the trolley: The ethics of autonomous vehicles in mundane situations. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21, 669–684.
Huff, C., & Tingley, D. (2015). ‘Who are these people?’ evaluating the demographic characteristics and political preferences of MTurk survey respondents. Research & Politics, 2(3), 1–12.
Jacobson, D. (2012). Moral dumbfounding and moral stupefaction. Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, 2, 289–316.
Kamtekar, R., & Nichols, S. (2019). Agent-regret and accidental agency. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 43, 181–202.
Katchadourian, H. (2010). Guilt. The bite of conscience. Stanford University Press.
Lerner, M. J. (2003). The justice motive: Where social psychologists found it, how they lost it, and why they may not find it again. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 7(4), 388–399.
Li, J., Zhao, X., Cho, M., Ju, W., & Malle, B. (2016). From trolley to autonomous vehicle: Perceptions of responsibility and moral norms in traffic accidents with self-driving cars. SAE Technical Paper. https://doi.org/10.4271/2016-01-0164
Lindsay-Hartz, J. (1984). Contrasting experiences of shame and guilt. American Behavioral Scientist, 27(6), 689–704.
McManus, R. M., & Rutchick, A. M. (2019). Autonomous vehicles and the attribution of moral responsibility. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 10, 345–352.
Nagel, T. (1979). Mortal questions. Cambridge University.
Nelissen, R. (2011). Guilt-induced self-punishment as a sign of remorse. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 3(2), 139–144.
Nelkin, D. K., (2021). Moral luck. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2021 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/moral-luck/.
Nelkin, D. (2013). Accountability and desert. The Journal of Ethics, 20(1), 173–189.
Nguyen, T., et al. (2019). Metamotivational knowledge of the role of high-level and low-level construal in goal-relevant task performance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 117(5), 876–899.
Nyholm, S., & Smids, J. (2016). The ethics of accident-algorithms for self-driving cars: An applied trolley problem? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 19, 1275–1289.
Peer, E., Rothschild, D. M. and Evernden, Z., Gordon, A., & Damer, E. (2021). MTurk, prolific or panels? Choosing the right audience for online research. Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3765448
Pöllänen, E., Read, G., Lane, B. R., Thompson, J., & Salmon, P. M. (2020). Who is to blame for crashes involving autonomous vehicles? Exploring blame attribution across the road transport system. Ergonomics. https://doi.org/10.1080/00140139.2020.1744064
Rajen, A. A., Kamtekar, R., Nichols, Sh., & Pizarro, D. (2021). “False positive” emotions, responsibility, and moral character. Cognition. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2021.104770
Riaz, F., & Niazi, M. A. (2016). Road collisions avoidance using vehicular cyber-physical systems: A taxonomy and review. Complex Adaptive Systems Modeling, 4, 1–34.
Rodríguez-Alcázar, J., Bermejo-Luque, L., & Molina-Pérez, A. (2020). Do automated vehicles face moral dilemmas? A plea for a political approach. Philosophy Technology. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-020-00432-5
Santoni de Sio, F. (2017). Killing by autonomous vehicles and the legal doctrine of necessity. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 20(2), 411–429.
Strawson, P. F. (1962). “Freedom and Resentment,” reprinted in P. F. Strawson, Freedom and resentment and other essays. (London, New York and Oxford: Methuen. 1974)
Struchiner, N., Almeida, G. F. C. F., & Hannikainen, I. R. (2020). Legal decision-making and the abstract/concrete paradox. Cognition, 205, 104421.
Sussman, D. (2018). Is agent-regret rational? Ethics, 128, 788–808.
Tangney, J. P., Stuewig, J., & Mashek, D. B. (2007). Moral emotions and moral behavior. Annual Review of Psychology, 58(1), 345–372.
Taylor, G. (1996). Guilt and remorse. In R. Harre & W. Gerrod Parrot (Eds.), The emotions: Social, cultural and biological dimensions (pp. 57–73). Sage Publications.
Taylor, G. (1985). Pride, shame and guilt. Oxford University Press.
Wallach, W., & Allen, C. (2009). Moral machines: Teaching robots right from wrong. Oxford University Press.
Willemsen, P. (2019). Omissions and their moral relevance. Assessing causal and moral responsibility for the things we fail to do. Mentis Verlag.
Williams, B. (1981). Moral luck. Cambridge University Press.
Wolf, S. (2000). The moral of moral luck. Philosophical Exchange, 31(1), 2–19.
Wu, C., Bayen, A. M., & Mehta, A. (2018). Stabilizing traffic with autonomous vehicles. In 2018 IEEE International conference on robotics and automation (ICRA) (pp. 1–7). IEEE.
Xu, Z., Zhang, K., Min, H., Wang, Z., Zhao, X., & Liu, P. (2018). What drives people to accept automated vehicles? Findings from a field experiment. Transportation Research Part c: Emerging Technologies, 95, 320–334.
Acknowledgements
We would like to thank the participants in the experimental-ethics session at the XIX Ethics and Political Philosophy Week, Ferrol (Spain), October 2018, particularly Carlos Thiebaut, Blanca Rodríguez and Mabel Holgado, for very helpful feedback. We would also like to thank Mabel Holgado for making us pay special attention to the relationship between guilt and remorse. This article is based on research funded by the Spanish Ministry of Science, Innovation, and Universities, reference number RTI2018-098882-B-I00 and reference number PID2020.119791RA.I00
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflicts of interest
All procedures performed in the studies involving human participants were in accordance with the ethical standards of the institutional and/or national research committee and with the 1964 Helsinki declaration and its later amendments or comparable ethical standards.
Informed consent
Informed consent was obtained from all individual participants included in the study.
Ethical approval
Ethical approval was given by the Consejo Superior de Investigaciones Científicas -Spanish National Research Council- (Committee Internal Code: 113/2020).
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Appendices
Appendix 1
Internal Meta-Analysis
Given the conflicting results, we conducted an internal meta-analysis (n = 768) to understand whether:
-
(1)
perceived guilt feelings in the Descriptive frame exceed prescribed guilt in the Normative frame, and
-
(2)
AV passengers are ascribed less guilt than conventional drivers.
Given differences in the scale length across studies, we first min–max normalized the dependent variable (i.e., from 0 to 1). A two-way ANOVA indicated that the effects of frame, F(1, 764) = 80.61, p < 0.001, eta2p = 0.11, and vehicle-type, F(1, 764) = 9.01, p = 0.003, eta2p = 0.01, were significant. The interaction was non-significant, F(1, 764) = 0.01, p = 0.92. Thus, though both effects were significant, the effect of frame was medium to large, whereas the effect of vehicle-type was small.
Appendix 2
Gender Differences in Guilt
We also examined whether there are gender differences in guilt ratings. To do this, we entered gender as a third factor, allowing it to interact with both experimental manipulations. We observed a main effect of gender, F(1, 757) = 13.33, p < 0.001, and a marginally significant interaction with frame, F(1, 757) = 2.82, p = 0.088. The effect of frame was larger among women, B = 0.21, t = 7.90, than among men, B = 0.14, t = 4.48, ps < 0.001. This difference was due to higher guilt ratings among women (M = 0.85) than among men (M = 0.74) in the Descriptive condition, t = 3.85, p < 0.001. The corresponding effect in the Normative condition was non-significant (M-Women = 0.65, M-Men = 0.61), t = 1.47, p = 0.14.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Aguiar, F., Hannikainen, I.R. & Aguilar, P. Guilt Without Fault: Accidental Agency in the Era of Autonomous Vehicles. Sci Eng Ethics 28, 11 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-022-00363-8
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-022-00363-8