Guilt Without Fault: Accidental Agency in the Era of Autonomous Vehicles | Science and Engineering Ethics
Skip to main content

Advertisement

Guilt Without Fault: Accidental Agency in the Era of Autonomous Vehicles

  • Original Research/Scholarship
  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The control principle implies that people should not feel guilt for outcomes beyond their control. Yet, the so-called ‘agent and observer puzzles’ in philosophy demonstrate that people waver in their commitment to the control principle when reflecting on accidental outcomes. In the context of car accidents involving conventional or autonomous vehicles (AVs), Study 1 established that judgments of responsibility are most strongly associated with expressions of guilt–over and above other negative emotions, such as sadness, remorse or anger. Studies 2 and 3 then confirmed that, while people generally endorse the control principle, and deny that occupants in an AV should feel guilt when involved in an accident, they nevertheless ascribe guilt to those same occupants. Study 3 also uncovered novel implications of the observer puzzle in the legal context: Passengers in an AV were seen as more legally liable than either passengers in a conventional vehicle, or even their drivers–especially when participants were prompted to reflect on the passengers’ affective experience of guilt. Our findings document an important conflict–in the context of AV accidents–between people’s prescriptive reasoning about responsibility and guilt on one hand, and their counter-normative experience of guilt on the other, with apparent implications for liability decisions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
¥17,985 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (Japan)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A fully autonomous vehicle has been defined by the United States of America’s National Highway Traffic Safety Administration (NHTSA 2016) as the following: “The vehicle is designed to perform all safety–critical driving functions and monitor roadway conditions for an entire trip. Such a design anticipates that the driver will provide destination or navigation input but is not expected to be available for control at any time during the trip. This includes both occupied and unoccupied vehicles. By design, safe operation rests solely on the automated vehicle system”. (NHTSA,2016).

  2. It seems that Mercedes-Benz intended to advertise its AV by ensuring that they would prioritize the occupant’s life above all: “Car and Driver reported on October 7 that Mercedes-Benz has already made a decision that its self-driving cars will always prioritize their own occupants over other road users. The automaker said it was wrong — and possibly illegal” (https://www.businessinsider.com/mercedes-denies-claim-its-driverless-car-will-prioritize-driver-safety-2016-10?IR=T, retrieved March 2, 2020).

  3. That the guilt feeling is appropriate does not mean that it is rational (as advocated by Sussman 2018), nor does it mean that it is irrational, as the logic of appropriateness is not necessarily linked to the logic of consequences (Balsige, 2014), which should be understood in this context as the (necessary) connection between the principle of control and the guilt feeling.

  4. The Ethics Committee of the Spanish Council for Scientific Research (CSIC)  has favorably evaluated this research (Committee Internal Code: 113/2020).

  5. “AAA’s [American Automobile Association] annual automated vehicle survey found that 71 percent of people are afraid to ride in fully self-driving vehicles” (Edmons, E., 2019). See also Zhigang et al., 2018.

References

  • Awad, E., Dsouza, S., Kim, R., Schultz, J., Henrich, J., Shariff, A., Bonnefon, J.-F., & Rahwan, I. (2018). The moral machine experiment. Nature, 563, 59–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Awad, E., Levine, S., Kleiman-Weiner, M., Dsouza, S., Tenenbaum, J. B., Shariff, A., Bonnefon, J.-F., & Rahwan, I. (2020). Drivers are blamed more than their automated cars when both make mistakes. Nature Human Behaviour, 4(2), 134–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balsiger, J. (2014). Logic of appropriateness. Encyclopedia Britannica. Available at http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/1937900/logic-ofappropriateness. Retrieved May 12, 2021.

  • Baumeister, R., Stillwell, A., & Heatherton, T. (1994). Guilt: An interpersonal approach. Psychological Bulletin, 115(2), 243–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennet, R., Vijaygopal, R., & Kottasz, R. (2020). Willingness of people who are blind to accept autonomous vehicles: An empirical investigation. Transportation Research Part f: Traffic Psychology and Behaviour, 69, 13–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bieker, S. (2012). Legal aspects of autonomous driving. Santa Clara Law Review, 52, 1146–1156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bissel, D., Birtchnell, T., Elliott, A., & Hsu, E. L. (2018). Autonomous automobilities: The social impact of driverless vehicles. Current Sociology, 68, 116–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonnefon, J.-F., Shariff, A., & Rahwan, I. (2016). The social dilemma of autonomous vehicles. Science, 352, 1573–1576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campos, A. S. (2013). Responsibility and justice in aristotle’s non-voluntary and mixed actions. Journal of Ancient Philosophy, 7, 100–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlsson, A. B. (2017). Blameworthiness as deserved guilt. Journal of Ethics, 21, 89–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coeckelbergh, M. (2020). AI Ethics, Mit Press.

  • Cordner, C. (2007). Guilt, remorse and victims. Philosophical Investigations, 30, 337–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Rivera, J. (1984). The structure of emotional relationships. Review of Personality & Social Psychology.

  • Deem, M. J., & Ramsey, G. (2016). Guilt by association? Philosophical Psychology, 4, 570–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edmons, E. (2019). Self-driving vehicles. https://newsroom.aaa.com/2019/03/americans-fear-self-driving-cars-survey/. Retrieved 5 July, 2021.

  • Enoch, D. (2012). Being responsible, taking responsibility, and penumbral agency. In U. Heuer & G. Lang (Ed.), Luck, value, and commitment: Themes from the ethics of Bernard Williams. Oxford University Press.

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge University Press

  • Gill, T. (2020). Blame it on the self-driving car: How autonomous vehicles can alter consumer morality. Journal of Consumer Research, 47(2), 272–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gill, T. (2021). Ethical dilemmas are really important to potential adopters of autonomous vehicles. Ethics and Information Technology. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-021-09605-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. S. (1992). Subjective guilt and responsibility. Mind, 101, 287–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, A. (2017). The sorrow and the shame of the accidental killer. The New Yorker, September 18.

  • Heuer, U. & Lang, G. (Eds.) (2011). Luck, value, and commitment - Themes from the ethics of Bernard Williams. Oxford University Press.

  • Hieronymi, P. (2004). The force and fairness of blame. Philosophical Perspectives, 18, 115–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Himmelreich, J. (2028). Never mind the trolley: The ethics of autonomous vehicles in mundane situations. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21, 669–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huff, C., & Tingley, D. (2015). ‘Who are these people?’ evaluating the demographic characteristics and political preferences of MTurk survey respondents. Research & Politics, 2(3), 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, D. (2012). Moral dumbfounding and moral stupefaction. Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, 2, 289–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamtekar, R., & Nichols, S. (2019). Agent-regret and accidental agency. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 43, 181–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katchadourian, H. (2010). Guilt. The bite of conscience. Stanford University Press.

  • Lerner, M. J. (2003). The justice motive: Where social psychologists found it, how they lost it, and why they may not find it again. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 7(4), 388–399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Li, J., Zhao, X., Cho, M., Ju, W., & Malle, B. (2016). From trolley to autonomous vehicle: Perceptions of responsibility and moral norms in traffic accidents with self-driving cars. SAE Technical Paper. https://doi.org/10.4271/2016-01-0164

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindsay-Hartz, J. (1984). Contrasting experiences of shame and guilt. American Behavioral Scientist, 27(6), 689–704.

  • McManus, R. M., & Rutchick, A. M. (2019). Autonomous vehicles and the attribution of moral responsibility. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 10, 345–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1979). Mortal questions. Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelissen, R. (2011). Guilt-induced self-punishment as a sign of remorse. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 3(2), 139–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, D. K., (2021). Moral luck. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2021 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/moral-luck/.

  • Nelkin, D. (2013). Accountability and desert. The Journal of Ethics, 20(1), 173–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nguyen, T., et al. (2019). Metamotivational knowledge of the role of high-level and low-level construal in goal-relevant task performance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 117(5), 876–899.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nyholm, S., & Smids, J. (2016). The ethics of accident-algorithms for self-driving cars: An applied trolley problem? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 19, 1275–1289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peer, E., Rothschild, D. M. and Evernden, Z., Gordon, A., & Damer, E. (2021). MTurk, prolific or panels? Choosing the right audience for online research. Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3765448

  • Pöllänen, E., Read, G., Lane, B. R., Thompson, J., & Salmon, P. M. (2020). Who is to blame for crashes involving autonomous vehicles? Exploring blame attribution across the road transport system. Ergonomics. https://doi.org/10.1080/00140139.2020.1744064

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rajen, A. A., Kamtekar, R., Nichols, Sh., & Pizarro, D. (2021). “False positive” emotions, responsibility, and moral character. Cognition. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2021.104770

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riaz, F., & Niazi, M. A. (2016). Road collisions avoidance using vehicular cyber-physical systems: A taxonomy and review. Complex Adaptive Systems Modeling, 4, 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodríguez-Alcázar, J., Bermejo-Luque, L., & Molina-Pérez, A. (2020). Do automated vehicles face moral dilemmas? A plea for a political approach. Philosophy Technology. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-020-00432-5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Santoni de Sio, F. (2017). Killing by autonomous vehicles and the legal doctrine of necessity. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 20(2), 411–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1962). “Freedom and Resentment,” reprinted in P. F. Strawson, Freedom and resentment and other essays. (London, New York and Oxford: Methuen. 1974)

  • Struchiner, N., Almeida, G. F. C. F., & Hannikainen, I. R. (2020). Legal decision-making and the abstract/concrete paradox. Cognition, 205, 104421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sussman, D. (2018). Is agent-regret rational? Ethics, 128, 788–808.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tangney, J. P., Stuewig, J., & Mashek, D. B. (2007). Moral emotions and moral behavior. Annual Review of Psychology, 58(1), 345–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, G. (1996). Guilt and remorse. In R. Harre & W. Gerrod Parrot (Eds.), The emotions: Social, cultural and biological dimensions (pp. 57–73). Sage Publications.

  • Taylor, G. (1985). Pride, shame and guilt. Oxford University Press.

  • Wallach, W., & Allen, C. (2009). Moral machines: Teaching robots right from wrong. Oxford University Press.

  • Willemsen, P. (2019). Omissions and their moral relevance. Assessing causal and moral responsibility for the things we fail to do. Mentis Verlag.

  • Williams, B. (1981). Moral luck. Cambridge University Press.

  • Wolf, S. (2000). The moral of moral luck. Philosophical Exchange, 31(1), 2–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, C., Bayen, A. M., & Mehta, A. (2018). Stabilizing traffic with autonomous vehicles. In 2018 IEEE International conference on robotics and automation (ICRA) (pp. 1–7). IEEE.

  • Xu, Z., Zhang, K., Min, H., Wang, Z., Zhao, X., & Liu, P. (2018). What drives people to accept automated vehicles? Findings from a field experiment. Transportation Research Part c: Emerging Technologies, 95, 320–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank the participants in the experimental-ethics session at the XIX Ethics and Political Philosophy Week, Ferrol (Spain), October 2018, particularly Carlos Thiebaut, Blanca Rodríguez and Mabel Holgado, for very helpful feedback. We would also like to thank Mabel Holgado for making us pay special attention to the relationship between guilt and remorse. This article is based on research funded by the Spanish Ministry of Science, Innovation, and Universities, reference number RTI2018-098882-B-I00 and reference number PID2020.119791RA.I00

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pilar Aguilar.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest

All procedures performed in the studies involving human participants were in accordance with the ethical standards of the institutional and/or national research committee and with the 1964 Helsinki declaration and its later amendments or comparable ethical standards.

Informed consent

Informed consent was obtained from all individual participants included in the study.

Ethical approval

Ethical approval was given by the Consejo Superior de Investigaciones Científicas -Spanish National Research Council- (Committee Internal Code: 113/2020).

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendices

Appendix 1

Internal Meta-Analysis

Given the conflicting results, we conducted an internal meta-analysis (n = 768) to understand whether:

  1. (1)

    perceived guilt feelings in the Descriptive frame exceed prescribed guilt in the Normative frame, and

  2. (2)

    AV passengers are ascribed less guilt than conventional drivers.

Given differences in the scale length across studies, we first min–max normalized the dependent variable (i.e., from 0 to 1). A two-way ANOVA indicated that the effects of frame, F(1, 764) = 80.61, p < 0.001, eta2p = 0.11, and vehicle-type, F(1, 764) = 9.01, p = 0.003, eta2p = 0.01, were significant. The interaction was non-significant, F(1, 764) = 0.01, p = 0.92. Thus, though both effects were significant, the effect of frame was medium to large, whereas the effect of vehicle-type was small.

Appendix 2

Gender Differences in Guilt

We also examined whether there are gender differences in guilt ratings. To do this, we entered gender as a third factor, allowing it to interact with both experimental manipulations. We observed a main effect of gender, F(1, 757) = 13.33, p < 0.001, and a marginally significant interaction with frame, F(1, 757) = 2.82, p = 0.088. The effect of frame was larger among women, B = 0.21, t = 7.90, than among men, B = 0.14, t = 4.48, ps < 0.001. This difference was due to higher guilt ratings among women (M = 0.85) than among men (M = 0.74) in the Descriptive condition, t = 3.85, p < 0.001. The corresponding effect in the Normative condition was non-significant (M-Women = 0.65, M-Men = 0.61), t = 1.47, p = 0.14.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Aguiar, F., Hannikainen, I.R. & Aguilar, P. Guilt Without Fault: Accidental Agency in the Era of Autonomous Vehicles. Sci Eng Ethics 28, 11 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-022-00363-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-022-00363-8

Keywords