Abstract
I challenge the dominant understanding of what it means to say two thoughts are associated. The two views that dominate the current literature treat association as a kind of mechanism that drives sequences of thought (often implicitly treating them so). The first, which I call reductive associationism, treats association as a kind of neural mechanism. The second treats association as a feature of the kind of psychological mechanism associative processing. Both of these views are inadequate. I argue that association should instead be seen as a highly abstract filler term, standing in for causal relations between representational states in a system. Associations, so viewed, could be implemented by many different mechanisms. I outline the role that this view gives associative models as part of a top-down characterization of psychological processes of any kind and of any complexity.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
The same question, whether association is merely ‘some’ causal relation between events, or a particular kind of intervening mechanism, applies to behaviorism. This can be loosely captured in the distinction between methodological behaviorism and radical behaviorism.
I do take the diversity of systems just mentioned to make even this weaker claim suspicious, but that will not figure into my argument against it here.
The requirement that mechanisms be ‘localized’ in some sense is controversial (Weiskopf 2011). But for present purposes, I need not be committed to any specific relation between cognitive models and neural realizers. All that my claim requires is that the psychological model implies something about the neural realizers.
This may not be true of certain uses of behaviorist models: if association is a relation between external stimuli (rather than representations), and one is not committed to any kind of realism about the association itself, then the model could be seen as a phenomenological model (see also footnote 1). Alternatively, an association between representations could be treated as the explanandum phenomenon (in fact, my view makes such a project more interesting than existing views; see Sect. 6). But this is not what associative models do.
For instance, I say here that my view takes associative models to be mechanism sketches while associative processing implies that they are mechanism schemata. One may perfectly reasonably draw the line in a different place, such that associative processing also implies that they are mechanism sketches. I draw the line where I do to highlight the differences that matter for the current discussion.
Hartley did distinguish associations between ideas from the neural vibrations that ‘cause’ them.
See Smolensky (1987). I focus on connectionist networks that are intended as models of some actual cognitive process. Many (perhaps most) connectionists do not interpret their models this way, instead treating them as how possibly models, or as explorations of the formalism. I set these networks aside. Note also that connectionists could build neural circuit models: my interest is in the content of the model, not the tradition in which it was built.
Note that a reductive associationist might take (say) connectionist models to imply a kind of processing which excludes symbolic processing, but not take this to imply that the process is simple (as with Abrahamson & Bechtel’s [1991] comment about ‘associationism with an intelligent face’ above). This ‘associative process’ may not face the problems discussed here, but still faces the problems of reductive associationism.
I discuss their arguments in Sect. 4.3.
This experiment actually used the related Japanese quail, not pigeons. But this is an integrated literature, largely driven by the same labs. They see the two species as related enough to bear on one another, so I will treat them that way as well.
I do not argue that there are no processes that fall in the space traditionally called ‘associative processing’ (as does, most famously, Gallistel 1990, 2000). That is to say, there may be processes for which no psychological model can be provided except for an associative model. But this discussion does imply that we should rethink the ways we engage with processes like this. The successful use of an associative model is not sufficient reason to consider a process to belong to this class. And these processes have no special claim to associative models; rather, they are defined by the failure of other kinds of models like cognitive models. A name that better reflects the actual basis of the class, like ‘non-cognitive processing,’ would lead to less confusion.
In effect, this is the inverse move of reductive associationism: Reductive associationists believe that association should be pitched at a lower level of description than it was traditionally (perhaps the level of ‘functional architecture,’ which Pylyshyn (1984) places below the algorithmic level). I argue that associative models should be pitched at a higher level of description (more like Pylyshyn’s ‘semantic’ level, similar to Marr’s (1982) computational level, though not exactly the same).
The Rescorla–Wagner model describes a process whereby associative strengths are adjusted based on errors in predictions that association generates. But, putting the point above more specifically, this should not be taken to imply a kind of mechanism of prediction error. That would run into my arguments against associative processing. In general, most in the field do not take the ‘prediction’ literally or realistically, even if they do so with the association (Danks 2013, 2014).
References
Akins, C. K., & Zentall, T. R. (1998). Imitation in Japanese quail: The role of reinforcement of demonstrator responding. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 5(4), 694–697.
Allen, C. (2006). Transitive inference in animals: Reasoning or conditioned associations. In S. Hurley & M. Nudds (Eds.), Rational animals (pp. 175–185). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Anderson, J. R., & Bower, G. H. (1973). Human associative memory. Washington, DC: Winston.
Baddeley, A. D., & Hitch, G. J. (1974). Working memory. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation (Vol. 8, pp. 47–89). New York: Academic Press.
Bechtel, W. (1985). Contemporary connectionism: Are the new parallel distributed processing models cognitive or associationist? Behaviorism, 13, 53–62.
Bechtel, W., & Abrahamson, A. (1991). Connectionism and the mind: An introduction to parallel processing in networks. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Beckers, T., & Vervliet, B. (2009). Commentary: The truth and value of theories of associative learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 200–201.
Buckner, C. (2011). Two approaches to the distinction between cognition and “mere association”. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 24(4), 314–348.
Buckner, C. (2013). A property cluster theory of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 1–30.
Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). After the philosophy of mind: Replacing scholasticism with science. Philosophy of Science, 75, 1–27.
Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (1993). Associative engine: Connectionism, concepts, and representational change. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clayton, N., Emery, N., & Dickinson, A. (2006). The rationality of animal memory: Complex caching strategies of western scrub jays. Rational animals, 197–216.
Cummins, R. (1983). The nature of psychological explanation. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Cummins, R. (2000). How does it work?” versus” What are the laws?”: Two conceptions of psychological explanation. In F. Keil & R. Wilsons (Eds.), Explanation and cognition (pp. 117–144). Cambridge: MIT Press.
Craver, C. F. (2006). When mechanistic models explain. Synthese, 153(3), 355–376.
Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Craver, C. F. (forthcoming). The explanatory power of network models. Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1086/687856.
Dacey, M. (2015). Associationism without associative links: Thomas Brown and the associationist project. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 54, 31–40.
Danks, D. (2013). Moving from levels & reduction to dimensions & constraints. In Proceedings of the 35th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 2124–2129).
Danks, D. (2014). Unifying the mind: Cognitive representations as graphical models. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Dellarosa, D. (1988). The psychological appeal of connectionism. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11(01), 28–29.
Dickinson, A. (1980). Contemporary animal learning theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dickinson, A. (2001). Causal learning: An associative analysis. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 54B(1), 3–25.
Dickinson, A. (2012). Associative learning and animal cognition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 367(1603), 2733–2742.
Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition, 28(1–2), 3–71.
Gallistel, C. R. (1990). The organization of learning. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.
Gallistel, C. R. (2000). The replacement of general-purpose learning models with adaptively specialized learning modules. In M. S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The cognitive neurosciences (2nd ed., pp. 1179–1191). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gallo, D. (2006). Associative illusions of memory: False memory research in DRM and related tasks. New York: Psychology Press.
Glennan, S. S. (2009). Counterfactual theories. In H. Beebee, P. Menzies, & C. Hitchcock (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 315–324). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gluck, M. A., & Thompson, R. F. (1987). Modeling the neural substrates of associative learning and memory: A computational approach. Psychological Review, 94(2), 176.
Hartley, D. (1749/1966). Observations on Man. Repr. Gainesville, Florida: Scholars’ Facsimiles & Reprints.
Hochstein, E. (2016). One mechanism, many models: A distributed theory of mechanistic explanation. Synthese, 193(5), 1387–1407.
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Le Pelley, M. E. (2014). Primate polemic: Commentary on Smith, Couchman, and Beran (2014). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 128(2), 132–134.
Mandelbaum, E. (2015a). Attitude, inference, association: On the propositional structure of implicit bias. Noûs. doi:10.1111/nous.12089
Mandelbaum, E. (2015b). Associationist theories of thought. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/associationist-thought/.
Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. New York: Henry Holt and Co., Inc.
Meltzoff, A. N. (1996). The human infant as imitative generalist: A 20-year progress report on infant imitation with implications for comparative psychology. In C. M. Heyes & B. G. Galef (Eds.), Social learning in animals: The roots of culture (pp. 347–370). New York: Academic Press.
Mitchell, C. J., De Houwer, J., & Lovibond, P. F. (2009). The propositional nature of human associative learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(02), 183–198.
Moore, B. R. (1992). Avian imitation and a new form of mimicry: Tracing the evolution of complex learning. Behaviour, 122, 231–263.
Newman, M. (2010). Networks: An introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Page, M. (2000). Connectionist modelling in psychology: A localist manifesto. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23(4), 443–467. discussion 467–512.
Papineau, D., & Heyes, C. (2006). Rational or associative? Imitation in Japanese quail. In S. Hurley & M. Nudds (Eds.), Rational animals (pp. 187–195). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Papini, M. R. (2008). Comparative psychology: Evolution and development of behavior. Routledge: Taylor & Francis.
Penn, D. C., & Povinelli, D. J. (2007). Causal cognition in human and nonhuman animals: A comparative, critical review. Annual review of psychology, 58, 97–118.
Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical computation: A mechanistic account. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Piccinini, G., & Bahar, S. (2013). Neural computation and the computational theory of cognition. Cognitive Science, 37(3), 453–488.
Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Quartz, S. R., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1997). The neural basis of cognitive development: A constructivist manifesto. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20(4), 537–556.
Rescorla, R. A. (1988). Pavlovian conditioning: It’s not what you think it is. American Psychologist, 43(3), 151.
Rescorla, R. A., & Wagner, A. R. (1972). A theory of Pavlovian conditioning: Variations in the effectiveness of reinforcement and nonreinforcement. In A. H. Black & W. F. Prokasy (Eds.), Classical conditioning II (pp. 64–99). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Saggerson, A. L., George, D. N., & Honey, R. C. (2005). Imitative learning of stimulus-response and response-outcome associations in pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 31(3), 289–300.
Schultz, W., Dayan, P., & Montague, P. R. (1997). A neural substrate of prediction and reward. Science, 275(5306), 1593–1599.
Shanks, D. R. (1994). Human associative learning. In N. J. Mackintosh (Ed.), Animal learning and cognition (2nd ed.). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Shanks, D. R. (1995). The psychology of associative learning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Shanks, D. R. (2007). Associationism and cognition: Human contingency learning at 25. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 60(3), 291–309.
Shettleworth, S. J. (2010). Cognition, evolution, and behavior. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Smith, J. D., Couchman, J. J., & Beran, M. J. (2014). Animal metacognition: A tale of two comparative psychologies. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 128(2), 115–131.
Smolensky, P. (1987). On the proper treatment of connectionism. Department of Computer Science, University of Colorado, Boulder.
Thorpe, W. H. (1963). Learning and instinct in animals (2nd ed.). London: Methuen.
Tolman, E. C. (1948). Cognitive maps in rats and men. Psychological Review, 55(4), 189.
Walters, E. T., Carew, T. J., & Kandel, E. R. (1981). Associative learning in Aplysia: Evidence for conditioned fear in an invertebrate. Science, 211(4481), 504–506.
Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Weiskopf, D. A. (2011). Models and mechanisms in psychological explanation. Synthese, 183(3), 313–338.
Williams, J. N. (2005). Associationism and connectionism. In K. E. Brown (Ed.), Encyclopaedia of language and linguistics (2nd ed., pp. 559–562). Oxford: Elsevier.
Zentall, T. R. (1996). An analysis of imitative learning in animals. In C. M. Heyes & B. G. Galef (Eds.), Social learning in animals: The roots of culture (pp. 221–243). New York: Academic Press.
Zentall, T. R., Sutton, J. E., & Sherburne, L. M. (1996). True imitative learning in pigeons. Psychological Science, 7(6), 343–346.
Acknowledgments
Thanks to Ron Mallon, Carl Craver, John Doris, David Danks, Cameron Buckner, Lauren Olin, Joe McCaffrey, and Marta Halina for helpful comments on drafts. Thanks to participants in various working groups and reading groups at WashU where I presented material related to this paper over the years, and to Gualtiero Piccinini and Daniel Povinelli for helpful discussions. Finally, I’d like to thank two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Dacey, M. Rethinking associations in psychology. Synthese 193, 3763–3786 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1167-0
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1167-0