Rethinking associations in psychology | Synthese
Skip to main content

Rethinking associations in psychology

  • Neuroscience and Its Philosophy
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I challenge the dominant understanding of what it means to say two thoughts are associated. The two views that dominate the current literature treat association as a kind of mechanism that drives sequences of thought (often implicitly treating them so). The first, which I call reductive associationism, treats association as a kind of neural mechanism. The second treats association as a feature of the kind of psychological mechanism associative processing. Both of these views are inadequate. I argue that association should instead be seen as a highly abstract filler term, standing in for causal relations between representational states in a system. Associations, so viewed, could be implemented by many different mechanisms. I outline the role that this view gives associative models as part of a top-down characterization of psychological processes of any kind and of any complexity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
¥17,985 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (Japan)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The same question, whether association is merely ‘some’ causal relation between events, or a particular kind of intervening mechanism, applies to behaviorism. This can be loosely captured in the distinction between methodological behaviorism and radical behaviorism.

  2. I do take the diversity of systems just mentioned to make even this weaker claim suspicious, but that will not figure into my argument against it here.

  3. The requirement that mechanisms be ‘localized’ in some sense is controversial (Weiskopf 2011). But for present purposes, I need not be committed to any specific relation between cognitive models and neural realizers. All that my claim requires is that the psychological model implies something about the neural realizers.

  4. This may not be true of certain uses of behaviorist models: if association is a relation between external stimuli (rather than representations), and one is not committed to any kind of realism about the association itself, then the model could be seen as a phenomenological model (see also footnote 1). Alternatively, an association between representations could be treated as the explanandum phenomenon (in fact, my view makes such a project more interesting than existing views; see Sect. 6). But this is not what associative models do.

  5. For instance, I say here that my view takes associative models to be mechanism sketches while associative processing implies that they are mechanism schemata. One may perfectly reasonably draw the line in a different place, such that associative processing also implies that they are mechanism sketches. I draw the line where I do to highlight the differences that matter for the current discussion.

  6. Hartley did distinguish associations between ideas from the neural vibrations that ‘cause’ them.

  7. See Smolensky (1987). I focus on connectionist networks that are intended as models of some actual cognitive process. Many (perhaps most) connectionists do not interpret their models this way, instead treating them as how possibly models, or as explorations of the formalism. I set these networks aside. Note also that connectionists could build neural circuit models: my interest is in the content of the model, not the tradition in which it was built.

  8. Note that a reductive associationist might take (say) connectionist models to imply a kind of processing which excludes symbolic processing, but not take this to imply that the process is simple (as with Abrahamson & Bechtel’s [1991] comment about ‘associationism with an intelligent face’ above). This ‘associative process’ may not face the problems discussed here, but still faces the problems of reductive associationism.

  9. I discuss their arguments in Sect. 4.3.

  10. This experiment actually used the related Japanese quail, not pigeons. But this is an integrated literature, largely driven by the same labs. They see the two species as related enough to bear on one another, so I will treat them that way as well.

  11. I do not argue that there are no processes that fall in the space traditionally called ‘associative processing’ (as does, most famously, Gallistel 1990, 2000). That is to say, there may be processes for which no psychological model can be provided except for an associative model. But this discussion does imply that we should rethink the ways we engage with processes like this. The successful use of an associative model is not sufficient reason to consider a process to belong to this class. And these processes have no special claim to associative models; rather, they are defined by the failure of other kinds of models like cognitive models. A name that better reflects the actual basis of the class, like ‘non-cognitive processing,’ would lead to less confusion.

  12. In effect, this is the inverse move of reductive associationism: Reductive associationists believe that association should be pitched at a lower level of description than it was traditionally (perhaps the level of ‘functional architecture,’ which Pylyshyn (1984) places below the algorithmic level). I argue that associative models should be pitched at a higher level of description (more like Pylyshyn’s ‘semantic’ level, similar to Marr’s (1982) computational level, though not exactly the same).

  13. The Rescorla–Wagner model describes a process whereby associative strengths are adjusted based on errors in predictions that association generates. But, putting the point above more specifically, this should not be taken to imply a kind of mechanism of prediction error. That would run into my arguments against associative processing. In general, most in the field do not take the ‘prediction’ literally or realistically, even if they do so with the association (Danks 2013, 2014).

References

  • Akins, C. K., & Zentall, T. R. (1998). Imitation in Japanese quail: The role of reinforcement of demonstrator responding. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 5(4), 694–697.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, C. (2006). Transitive inference in animals: Reasoning or conditioned associations. In S. Hurley & M. Nudds (Eds.), Rational animals (pp. 175–185). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J. R., & Bower, G. H. (1973). Human associative memory. Washington, DC: Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baddeley, A. D., & Hitch, G. J. (1974). Working memory. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation (Vol. 8, pp. 47–89). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (1985). Contemporary connectionism: Are the new parallel distributed processing models cognitive or associationist? Behaviorism, 13, 53–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamson, A. (1991). Connectionism and the mind: An introduction to parallel processing in networks. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckers, T., & Vervliet, B. (2009). Commentary: The truth and value of theories of associative learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 200–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2011). Two approaches to the distinction between cognition and “mere association”. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 24(4), 314–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2013). A property cluster theory of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 1–30.

  • Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). After the philosophy of mind: Replacing scholasticism with science. Philosophy of Science, 75, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1993). Associative engine: Connectionism, concepts, and representational change. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N., Emery, N., & Dickinson, A. (2006). The rationality of animal memory: Complex caching strategies of western scrub jays. Rational animals, 197–216.

  • Cummins, R. (1983). The nature of psychological explanation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (2000). How does it work?” versus” What are the laws?”: Two conceptions of psychological explanation. In F. Keil & R. Wilsons (Eds.), Explanation and cognition (pp. 117–144). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2006). When mechanistic models explain. Synthese, 153(3), 355–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (forthcoming). The explanatory power of network models. Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1086/687856.

  • Dacey, M. (2015). Associationism without associative links: Thomas Brown and the associationist project. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 54, 31–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danks, D. (2013). Moving from levels & reduction to dimensions & constraints. In Proceedings of the 35th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 2124–2129).

  • Danks, D. (2014). Unifying the mind: Cognitive representations as graphical models. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dellarosa, D. (1988). The psychological appeal of connectionism. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11(01), 28–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickinson, A. (1980). Contemporary animal learning theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickinson, A. (2001). Causal learning: An associative analysis. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 54B(1), 3–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickinson, A. (2012). Associative learning and animal cognition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 367(1603), 2733–2742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition, 28(1–2), 3–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. R. (1990). The organization of learning. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. R. (2000). The replacement of general-purpose learning models with adaptively specialized learning modules. In M. S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The cognitive neurosciences (2nd ed., pp. 1179–1191). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallo, D. (2006). Associative illusions of memory: False memory research in DRM and related tasks. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. S. (2009). Counterfactual theories. In H. Beebee, P. Menzies, & C. Hitchcock (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 315–324). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gluck, M. A., & Thompson, R. F. (1987). Modeling the neural substrates of associative learning and memory: A computational approach. Psychological Review, 94(2), 176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartley, D. (1749/1966). Observations on Man. Repr. Gainesville, Florida: Scholars’ Facsimiles & Reprints.

  • Hochstein, E. (2016). One mechanism, many models: A distributed theory of mechanistic explanation. Synthese, 193(5), 1387–1407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Pelley, M. E. (2014). Primate polemic: Commentary on Smith, Couchman, and Beran (2014). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 128(2), 132–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2015a). Attitude, inference, association: On the propositional structure of implicit bias. Noûs. doi:10.1111/nous.12089

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2015b). Associationist theories of thought. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/associationist-thought/.

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. New York: Henry Holt and Co., Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N. (1996). The human infant as imitative generalist: A 20-year progress report on infant imitation with implications for comparative psychology. In C. M. Heyes & B. G. Galef (Eds.), Social learning in animals: The roots of culture (pp. 347–370). New York: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, C. J., De Houwer, J., & Lovibond, P. F. (2009). The propositional nature of human associative learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(02), 183–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, B. R. (1992). Avian imitation and a new form of mimicry: Tracing the evolution of complex learning. Behaviour, 122, 231–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, M. (2010). Networks: An introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Page, M. (2000). Connectionist modelling in psychology: A localist manifesto. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23(4), 443–467. discussion 467–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D., & Heyes, C. (2006). Rational or associative? Imitation in Japanese quail. In S. Hurley & M. Nudds (Eds.), Rational animals (pp. 187–195). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Papini, M. R. (2008). Comparative psychology: Evolution and development of behavior. Routledge: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penn, D. C., & Povinelli, D. J. (2007). Causal cognition in human and nonhuman animals: A comparative, critical review. Annual review of psychology, 58, 97–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical computation: A mechanistic account. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Bahar, S. (2013). Neural computation and the computational theory of cognition. Cognitive Science, 37(3), 453–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quartz, S. R., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1997). The neural basis of cognitive development: A constructivist manifesto. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20(4), 537–556.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, R. A. (1988). Pavlovian conditioning: It’s not what you think it is. American Psychologist, 43(3), 151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, R. A., & Wagner, A. R. (1972). A theory of Pavlovian conditioning: Variations in the effectiveness of reinforcement and nonreinforcement. In A. H. Black & W. F. Prokasy (Eds.), Classical conditioning II (pp. 64–99). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saggerson, A. L., George, D. N., & Honey, R. C. (2005). Imitative learning of stimulus-response and response-outcome associations in pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 31(3), 289–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schultz, W., Dayan, P., & Montague, P. R. (1997). A neural substrate of prediction and reward. Science, 275(5306), 1593–1599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shanks, D. R. (1994). Human associative learning. In N. J. Mackintosh (Ed.), Animal learning and cognition (2nd ed.). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanks, D. R. (1995). The psychology of associative learning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shanks, D. R. (2007). Associationism and cognition: Human contingency learning at 25. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 60(3), 291–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shettleworth, S. J. (2010). Cognition, evolution, and behavior. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. D., Couchman, J. J., & Beran, M. J. (2014). Animal metacognition: A tale of two comparative psychologies. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 128(2), 115–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smolensky, P. (1987). On the proper treatment of connectionism. Department of Computer Science, University of Colorado, Boulder.

  • Thorpe, W. H. (1963). Learning and instinct in animals (2nd ed.). London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tolman, E. C. (1948). Cognitive maps in rats and men. Psychological Review, 55(4), 189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walters, E. T., Carew, T. J., & Kandel, E. R. (1981). Associative learning in Aplysia: Evidence for conditioned fear in an invertebrate. Science, 211(4481), 504–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weiskopf, D. A. (2011). Models and mechanisms in psychological explanation. Synthese, 183(3), 313–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. N. (2005). Associationism and connectionism. In K. E. Brown (Ed.), Encyclopaedia of language and linguistics (2nd ed., pp. 559–562). Oxford: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zentall, T. R. (1996). An analysis of imitative learning in animals. In C. M. Heyes & B. G. Galef (Eds.), Social learning in animals: The roots of culture (pp. 221–243). New York: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zentall, T. R., Sutton, J. E., & Sherburne, L. M. (1996). True imitative learning in pigeons. Psychological Science, 7(6), 343–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Ron Mallon, Carl Craver, John Doris, David Danks, Cameron Buckner, Lauren Olin, Joe McCaffrey, and Marta Halina for helpful comments on drafts. Thanks to participants in various working groups and reading groups at WashU where I presented material related to this paper over the years, and to Gualtiero Piccinini and Daniel Povinelli for helpful discussions. Finally, I’d like to thank two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mike Dacey.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dacey, M. Rethinking associations in psychology. Synthese 193, 3763–3786 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1167-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1167-0

Keywords