Abstract
How questions are understudied in philosophy and linguistics. They can be answered in very different ways, some of which are poorly understood. Jaworski (Synthese 166:133–155, 2009) identifies several types: (i) ‘manner’, (ii) ‘method, means or mechanism’, (iii) ‘cognitive resolution’, and develops a logic designed to enable us to distinguish among them. Some key questions remain open, however, in particular, whether these distinctions derive from an ambiguity in how, from differences in the logical structure of the question or from contextual underspecification. Arguing from two classes of responses, adverbs and by gerunds, I give the answer that the logical structure of the question is indeed relevant: loosely, manners are adjuncts but methods are arguments.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
The example is easily replicated:
-
(i)
– How do hedgehogs make love?
– Very, very carefully! [http://jokes4us.com/animaljokes/hedgehogjokes.html]
-
(i)
To be exact, what the predicate is combined with is the trace of how; cf. Sect. 4.
I follow common practice in linguistics since Kratzer (1996) in assuming that the agent is introduced by a separate functor above the verb phrase.
The types s, e, v, and t are the types of points of evaluation (worlds), individuals, events, and truth values, respectively; any type \(\langle a,\!b\rangle \) is the type of functions from things of type a to things of type b, so that, for example, \(\langle v,\!t\rangle \) is the type of functions from events to truth values, equivalently, the type of sets of events.
The metalinguistic functor \([\![\,\cdot \,]\!]\) maps an expression to its meaning, or intension; when relativized to a point of evaluation, or world, w, the output is the expression’s denotation, or extension, at that point. The metalanguage \(\lambda \) represents functional abstraction, so that the definiens stands for a function from events (e) to truth values, equivalently, a set of events.
The symbol ‘?’ indicates that the sentence is only marginally acceptable.
In a given case, RP will be determined by \(\phi \) and x; for example, if \(\phi \) is break a promise, RP might be ‘conflict with a promise made by x’. Mostly, though, RP will be more complex and difficult to spell out (Bennett 1994, p. 36).
Key elements of the analysis to be presented were developed in (Sæbø 2008).
The logical-type subscript \(\langle s, \langle v,t \rangle \rangle \) restricts the variable P to functions from worlds, or points of evaluation more generally, to sets of events; that is, to properties of events.
Causation is usually conceived in terms of counterfactual dependence.
The symbol ‘#’ indicates semantic anomaly.
I am indebted to Hedde Zijlstra for pointing this out.
The composition principle at work in this step is Intensional Functional Application (Heim and Kratzer 1998, p. 308)
On the notion of lexical coercion, see, e.g., Asher (2011, p. 214ff).
In (42) and (44), g is the current variable assignment, whereas w is the current world. The representations in (44) are a bit simplified; P(e), g(1)(e), and \(\mathtt{Become}(\mathtt{prince}(b))(f)\) are short for, respectively, \(\lambda i \,P_i(e)\), \(\lambda i \,g(1)_i(e)\), and \(\lambda i \, [\mathtt{Become}_i(\mathtt{prince}_i(b))(f)]\).
A brief review of the Groenendijk and Stokhof theory is given in an Appendix.
That the trace variable has the type of sets of events is to say that the value assigned to it by an assignment function g relative to a point of evaluation w, \(g(1)_w\) (its extension at g and w, \([\![\,\)t\(_1\,]\!]^{g,w}\)), is a set of events. The value assigned to it by g as such, g(1) (its intension at g, \([\![\,\)t\(_1\,]\!]^{g}\)), is a property of events, a function from points of evaluation to sets of events.
‘Extensional’ criterion predicates do seem to exist, though, like stand out, which seems to only require a set of events, states, or individuals, a case I will return to in Sect. 4.3.
Schnieder (2009, p. 664) takes an example of this kind to indicate that ‘only an explanatory how-she-did-it yields a correct ‘by’-statement’.
For discussions of modifiers and composition principles, see Castroviejo and Gehrke (2014) and Morzycki (to appear, chapter 5, sections 3 and 4).
Where the method of killing Holofernes is implicitly existentially quantified over, cf. (46) in section 4.2.
Jaworski (2009), who introduced the distinction, subdivides what I call method questions, ‘analytic’ questions in his term, into ‘means’, ‘mechanism’ and ‘method’ questions.
The added complexity is evident in Jaworski’s analysis in terms of analysis schemes.
References
Aloni, M. (2001). Quantification under Conceptual Covers. PhD dissertation, University of Amsterdam.
Anscombe, G. (1963). Intention (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.
Asher, N. (2011). Lexical meaning in Context: A web of words. Cambridge: CUP.
Asher, N., & Lascarides, A. (1998). Questions in dialogue. Linguistics and Philosophy, 21, 237–309.
Belnap, N., & Steel, T. (1976). The logic of questions. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Bennett, J. (1994). The ‘Namely’ analysis of the ‘By’-locution. Linguistics and Philosophy, 17, 29–51.
Castroviejo, E., & Gehrke, B. (2014). Modification at the interfaces: An introduction. Lingua, 149A, 1–16.
Cross, C. (1991). Explanation and the theory of questions. Erkenntnis, 34, 237–260.
Danto, A. (1965). Basic actions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 2, 141–148.
Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons, and causes. In R. Blinkley, R. Bronaugh, & A. Marras (Eds.), Agent, action, and reason (pp. 3–25). Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Davidson, D. (1967). The logical form of action sentences. In N. Rescher (Ed.), The logic of decision and action (pp. 81–95). Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.
Dekker, P. (2007). Optimal inquisitive discourse. In M. Aloni, A. Butler, & P. Dekker (Eds.), Questions in dynamic semantics (pp. 83–101). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Dong, H. (2009). Issues in the semantics of mandarin questions. PhD thesis, Cornell.
Dowty, D. (1979). Word meaning and montague grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Eckardt, R. (1998). Events, adverbs, and other things. issues in the semantics of manner adverbs. Tübingen: Niemeyer.
George, B. R. (2011). Question embedding and the semantics of answers. PhD dissertation, UCLA.
Ginzburg, J. (1995). Resolving questions, I. Linguistics and Philosophy, 18, 459–527.
Goldman, A. (1970). A theory of human action. New York: Prentice-Hall.
Groenendijk, J. & Stokhof, M. (1984). Studies in the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers. PhD dissertation, University of Amsterdam.
Hamblin, C. (1973). Questions in Montague english. Foundations of Language, 10, 41–53.
Heim, I., & Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics in generative grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hornsby, J. & Goulder, N. (2011). Action. In Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/V001. Accessed November 30, 2014.
Jaworski, W. (2009). The logic of how-questions. Synthese, 166, 133–155.
Karttunen, L. (1977). Syntax and semantics of questions. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1, 1–44.
Kearns, K. (2003). Durative achievements and individual-level predicates on events. Linguistics and Philosophy, 26, 595–635.
Kennedy, C. (2007). Vagueness and grammar: The semantics of relative and absolute gradable adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 1–45.
Kratzer, A. (1996). Severing the external argument from its verb. In J. Rooryck & L. Zaring (Eds.), Phrase Structure and the Lexicon (pp. 109–137). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Maienborn, C., & Schäfer, M. (2011). Adverbs and adverbials. In C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, & P. Portner (Eds.), Semantics: An International Handbook of Natural Language Meaning (pp. 1390–1420). Berlin: de Gruyter Mouton.
Moltmann, Friederike. (2003). Events as derived objects. In C. Beyssade, et al. (Eds.), Empirical issues in syntax and semantics 4 (pp. 189–204). Paris: Presses Universitaires de Paris Sorbonne.
Morzycki, M. (to appear). Modification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rothstein, S. (2004). Structuring events: A study in the semantics of aspect. Oxford: Blackwell.
Ryle, G. (1946). Knowing how and knowing that. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 46, 1–16.
Sæbø, K. J. (2008). The structure of criterion predicates. In J. Dölling, T. Heyde-Zybatow, & M. Schäfer (Eds.), Event structures in linguistic form and interpretation (pp. 127–147). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Schnieder, B. (2009). By. Linguistics and Philosophy, 31, 649–669.
Searle, J. (2001). The rationality of action. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Šimík, Radek. (2011). Introduction to the semantics of questions. České Budějovice: EGG summer school.
Stanley, J. (2011a). Knowing (How). Noûs, 45, 207–238.
Stanley, J. (2011b). Know how. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 411–444.
Thomason, R., & Stalnaker, R. (1973). A semantic theory of adverbs. Linguistic Inquiry, 4, 195–220.
Thomson, J. J. (1977). Acts and other events. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: OUP.
van Rooy, R. (2003). Questioning to resolve decision problems. Linguistics and Philosophy, 26, 727–763.
Vendler, Z. (1957). Verbs and times. The Philosophical Review, 66, 143–160.
Wreen, M. (1987). Two ‘by’ ways. Analysis, 47, 120–124.
Wunderlich, D. (1997). Cause and the structure of verbs. Linguistic Inquiry, 28, 27–68.
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to the audiences at the Göteborg PhilLang Seminar on May 19, 2014, and at the Göttingen Linguistics Colloquium on October 29, 2014, for valuable comments and suggestions.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Appendix: Building how questions
Appendix: Building how questions
Here I give a brief outline of the building blocks of the meaning of a question in general and a how question in particular, and how they are put together, in a compositional version of the theory of Groenendijk and Stokhof (1984), in main part due to Šimík (2011). I illustrate the general model by reference to the simplest case of wh- questions, who questions, before turning to how.
1.1 The semantics of a who question
Consider (58) and its logical form (59).
The extensions of who\(_1\), the raised pronoun binding the trace \(\hbox {t}_1\), and \(\hbox {Q}_\mathrm{who}\), the relevant covert question operator, are given in (60) and (61) (where a is the type of variable assignments and the domain restriction to humans is ignored).
-
(60)
\([\![\,\hbox {who}_i\,]\!]^{g,w_0} \, = \, \lambda \phi _{a(st)} \lambda w \lambda x_e \, \phi _w^{g[i\rightarrow x]}\)
-
(61)
\([\![\,\hbox {Q}_\mathrm{who}\,]\!]^{g,w_0} \, = \, \lambda P_{s(et)} \lambda w \ P_w=P_{w_0}\)
Piecing the extensions of all terminal and branching nodes in (59) together, we arrive at (62) as the extension of (58) at the point of evaluation \(w_0\):
-
(62)
\(\lambda w \,[\, \lambda x \,\exists e\!<\!n \ \mathrm{kiss}_w(x)(e) \wedge \mathtt{agent}_w(e)(b) \ = \lambda x \,\exists e\!<\!n \ \mathrm{kiss}_{w_0}(x)(e) \wedge \mathtt{agent}_{w_0}(e)(b) \,]\)
The corresponding intension is an equivalence relation between points of evaluation. As such, it induces a partition of Logical Space; if the domain contains just 3 individuals, a partition with 8 cells, where each is a complete answer; cf., e.g., Table 1.
1.2 The semantics of a manner how question
Consider now (63) and its logical form (64) (in a one-dimensional notation).
-
(63)
how did Belle kiss the Beast
-
(64)
\(\hbox {Q}_\mathrm{how}\) [ \(\hbox {how}_1\) [ Tense [ Belle [ Voice [[ kiss Beast ] \(\hbox {t}_1\) ]]]]]
The extension of the raised how\(_1\) binding the trace \(\hbox {t}_1\) and the covert question operator of the appropriate type, \(\hbox {Q}_\mathrm{how}\), are given in (65) and (66).
-
(65)
\([\![\,\hbox {how}_i\,]\!]^{g,w_0} \, = \, \lambda \phi _{a(st)} \lambda w \lambda m_{s(v t)} \, \phi _w^{g[i\rightarrow m]}\)
-
(66)
\([\![\,\hbox {Q}_\mathrm{how}\,]\!]^{g,w_0} \, = \, \lambda M_{s((s(v t))t)} \lambda w \ M_w=M_{w_0}\)
Piecing the extensions of all terminal and branching nodes in (64) together, we arrive at (67) as the extension of (63) at the point of evaluation \(w_0\):
-
(67)
\(\lambda w \,[\, \lambda P \,\exists e\!<\!n \ \mathrm{kiss}_w(b_1)(e) \wedge \mathtt{agent}_w(e)(b_2) \wedge P_w(e) = \lambda P \,\exists e\!<\!n \ \mathrm{kiss}_{w_0}(b_1)(e) \wedge \mathtt{agent}_{w_0}(e)(b_2) \wedge P_{w_0}(e) \,]\)
Suppose—unrealistically, but anyway—that there are 3 relevant and suitable properties of events, the corresponding intension induces a partition of Logical Space with 8 cells, where each cell is a complete answer; cf., e.g., Table 2.
1.3 The semantics of a method how question
Consider (68) and its logical form (69), essentially the same structure as (64):
-
(68)
how did Belle turn the Beast into a prince
-
(69)
\(\hbox {Q}_\mathrm{how}\) [ \(\hbox {how}_1\) [ Tense [ Belle [ Voice [[ turn [ Beast into a prince ]] \(\hbox {t}_1\) ]]]]]
The semantics is different, though; while [ kiss Beast ] denotes a set of events which intersects with the extension of \(\hbox {t}_1\), [ turn [ Beast into a prince ]] denotes a function from properties of events which applies to the intension of \(\hbox {t}_1\). Thus although how and the covert question operator \(\hbox {Q}_{\mathrm{how}}\) continue to have the meaning specified in (65) and (66), the extension of (68) at \(w_0\) becomes (70) (note that neither the relation between propositions \(\mathtt{Cause}_w\) nor the function from sets of states to sets of events \(\mathtt{Become}_w\) for a given w is spelt out here):
-
(70)
\(\lambda w \,[ \,\lambda P \,\exists e <n \,\exists f\,\mathtt{Cause}_w(\lambda i [ \mathtt{Become}_i(\mathtt{prince}_i(b_1))(f)])(\lambda j P_j(e)) \wedge \mathtt{agent}_w(e)(b_2) \, = \lambda P \,\exists e \!<\!n \,\exists f\,\mathtt{Cause}_{w_0}(\lambda i [ \mathtt{Become}_i(\mathtt{prince}_i(b_1))(f)])(\lambda j P_j(e)) \wedge \mathtt{agent}_{w_0}(e)(b_2) \,]\)
As usual, the partition of Logical Space induced by the corresponding intension will, if there are 3 relevant and suitable properties of events, consist of 8 cells, each a complete answer to the question, for example, those in Table 3.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Sæbø, K.J. “How” questions and the manner–method distinction. Synthese 193, 3169–3194 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0924-9
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0924-9