Abstract
In English, in order to speak about Arthur’s attitudes, we use sentences like “Arthur believes that natural language is messy”. For sentences of this kind we have a standard theory, according to which the ‘that’-clause ‘that natural language is messy’ denotes a proposition. As Prior showed for the first time, the standard theory appears to be at odds with some linguistic data. Geach and Prior both assumed that linguistic data are to be taken as reliable guides to a correct semantic account and I will start by raising some worries concerning their methodology. Because of these data, Prior and Geach suggested some non-standard accounts. I will then show that if we take linguistic data seriously, their non-standard accounts do not fare any better than the standard theory. My general conclusion will thus not only be that Prior’s and Geach’s methodology is disputable, but also that their conclusions do not seem to follow even if we grant the reliability of their methodology.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
They discussed the theory several times in a correspondence which started in the Fifties and ended only with Prior’s death. The theory was, as Geach said, an “old wrangle of ours” (1966a).
Thanks to Max Cresswell for suggesting this example.
I am not following Geach’s own terminology. Geach (1972), p. 168 distinguished between Propositions and propositions: Propositions are the abstract creatures of the darkness, while propositions are sentences taken together with their meanings. Using his terminology, his account is in terms of propositions.
Geach (1963b) adds: “I have now, I think, better reasons (than that I seemed to hear the logical gears crushingly changed) for segregating the that clauses after “verbs of saying and thinking” as grammarians say from those after ‘prevent’, ‘bring about’, etc. and verbs for pro and contra attitudes. But my views haven’t crystallized out yet”. These better reasons cannot unfortunately be found either in the published or unpublished works.
For a more recent, similar account, see Parsons (1993).
When ‘that’-clauses flank only one side of ‘is’, the sentence is generally grammatical:
That natural language is messy is the most significant proposition in this paper.
One may then hold that ‘that’-clauses sometimes can and sometimes cannot flank identity. But one may also instead hold that ‘that’-clauses never flank identity and urge that in the cases in which they seem to be able to flank identity, the predicate does not really designate identity. According to Pryor (2007), for example, in the case above in this note ‘is’ is to be taken to be the so-called specificational copula. Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this issue.
As Geach told us, the relation between identity and singular terms goes back to Frege. For an example of Geach on identity and Frege, but unfortunately not on ‘that’-clauses, see Geach (1975).
In a first draft of the typescript of Objects of Thought, Prior seems to hold that the standard theory is acceptable for natural languages. He wrote (n.d. a; 106): “Grammatically the word ‘that’ undoubtedly does have the function of constituting a kind of name or quasi-name out of a sentence. Given the sentence ‘grass is green’, for example, we can construct the expression ‘that grass is green’ which may function as the grammatical subject or object of a longer sentence”. But this bit disappeared from the typescript.
In passing, it should be noted that in the unpublished Prior (n.d. b) but only there and deleted also there, Prior found it also “not implausible” to hold, together with the logicians of Port-Royal, that for propositional attitude sentences “the complexity ... lies not in the terms but in the copula”. According to this account
Arthur believes that natural language is messy
is to be analysed as
Natural language is-believed-by-Arthur-to-be messy.
It is clear that this is, again, at odds with Syntactic Unity: in
Arthur believes that natural language is messy and Peter too,
‘too’ can stand for ‘believes that natural language is messy’, so that ‘Arthur’ and ‘believes’ do not go together in a unit.
Another famous rejection of thesis (a) is Russell (1910)’s multiple relation theory, according to which
Arthur believes that natural language is messy
should be taken to express a multiple relation holding among Arthur, language and the property of being messy. Clearly, also Russell’s account is at odds with Syntactic Unity.
On the standard account of definite descriptions, definite descriptions also are quantified phrases. If this is correct, then definite descriptions are another example of quantified phrases that can flank identity, as shown by the perfect grammaticality of
The proposition that natural language is messy is the proposition that natural language is messy.
Thanks again to an anonymous referee for stressing this point.
One may think that the quantificational account is in conflict with a new datum. For according to this account,
Arthur fears that natural language is messy
should be taken as tantamount to
Arthur fears a that natural language is messy,
which is a quantified sentence. One may then think that since the quantifier ranges over the different objects of the attitudes, then in substituting a description for one of those objects I should have to obtain a sentence having the same truth-conditions, but I do not. For example, if Arthur fears that natural language is messy he does not fear a proposition. But this problem is quickly solved by holding that in the context of different predicates, the variables range over objects of different kinds: in the context of ‘to fear’, over states of affair, while in the context of ‘to believe’, over propositions.
Also Kenny (1963), p. 145 pointed out to Prior that in taking propositional attitude sentences as quantificational, only objectual quantifiers are needed.
References
Bach, K. (1997). Do belief reports report belief? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 78(3), 215–241.
Boh, I. (1993). Epistemic logic in the later middle ages. London: Routledge.
Geach, P. T. (1957). Mental acts. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Geach, P.T. (1961). Geach to Prior 24.10.1961. 979 Virtual Lab for Prior Studies.
Geach, P.T. (1962). Geach to Prior 3.10.1962. 989 Virtual Lab for Prior Studies.
Geach, P.T. (1963a). Geach to Prior 31.10.1963. 993 Virtual Lab for Prior Studies.
Geach, P.T. (1963b). Geach to Prior 25.11.1963. 995 Virtual Lab for Prior Studies.
Geach, P. T. (1965). Assertion. Philosophical Review, 74(4), 449–465.
Geach, P.T. (1966a). Geach to Prior 9.3.1966. 1020 Virtual Lab for Prior Studies.
Geach, P.T. (1966b). Geach to Prior 15.3.1966. 1021 Virtual Lab for Prior Studies.
Geach, P. T. (1972). The identity of propositions. In P. T. Geach (Ed.), Logic matters (pp. 166–174). Blakwell: Oxford.
Geach, P. T. (1975). Names and identity. In S. Guttenplan (Ed.), Mind and language (pp. 139–158). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hofweber, T. (2006). Schiffer’s new theory of propositions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73(1), 211–217.
Kenny, A. (1963). Oratio obliqua. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 37, 127–146.
Künne, W. (2003). Conceptions of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Moltmann, F. (2003). Propositional attitudes without propositions. Synthese, 135(1), 77–118.
Parsons, T. (1993). On denoting propositions and facts. Philosophical Perspectives, 7, 441–460.
Prior, A. N. (1963a). Is the concept of referential opacity really necessary? Acta Philosophica Fennica, 16, 189–199.
Prior, A. N. (1963b). Indirect speech again. Philosophical Studies, 14(1/2), 12–15.
Prior, A. N. (1963c). Oratio obliqua. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 37, 115–126.
Prior, A. N. (1964). Indirect speech and extensionality. Philosophical Studies, 15(3), 35–40.
Prior, A. N. (1968). Intentionality and intensionality. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 42, 91–106.
Prior, A.N. (1971). In P. T. Geach & A. Kenny (Eds.). Objects of Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Prior, A.N. (1976). In P. T. Geach & A. Kenny (Eds.). The doctrine of propositions and terms. London: Duckworth.
Prior, A.N. (n.d. a). Parts of Speech. (Parts of Speech (typed), 104; Parts of Speech HW II, 106; Parts of Speech: Rudiments of a Logic of Belief and Assertion, 107; Parts of Speech: Objects of Thought, 108. Virtual Lab for Prior Studies).
Prior, A.N. (n.d. b). Compound and complex propositions. 112 Virtual Lab for Prior Studies.
Pryor, J. (2007). Reasons and that-clauses. Philosophical Issues, 17(1), 217–244.
Recanati, F. (2004). ‘That’-clauses as existential quantifiers. Analysis, 64(3), 229–235.
Rosefeldt, T. (2008). ‘That’-clauses and non-nominal quantification. Philosophical Studies, 137(3), 301–333.
Russell, B. (1910). On the nature of truth and falsehood. In B. Russell (Ed.), Philosophical essays (pp. 147–159). London: Longmans, Green.
Salmon, N. (1983). Frege’s puzzle. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Scheffler, I. (1954). An inscriptional approach to indirect quotation. Analysis, 14(4), 83–90.
Schiffer, S. (2003). The things we mean. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schnieder, B. (2006). ‘By Leibniz’s Law’: Remarks on a fallacy. Philosophical Quarterly, 56(222), 39–54.
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Per Hasle, Peter Øhrstrøm, Jørgen Albretsen and all the people involved in The Virtual Lab for Prior Studies. They made it possible for me to have access to Prior’s Nachlass and in particular to the Geach–Prior correspondence, on which this work is based. I am indebted to Mark Textor for discussion of some of the main ideas presented here. Warm thanks, moreover, to the audience of the Arthur Prior Centenary Conference for their interesting remarks and in particular to Max Creswell, who helped me in understanding some delicate details. Gabriele Galluzzo helped me in understanding how to approach the manuscripts. Finally, I am grateful to an anonymous referee for her/his insightful comments.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Felappi, G. Why fuss about these quirks of the vernacular? Propositional attitude sentences in Prior’s nachlass . Synthese 193, 3521–3534 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0903-1
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0903-1