Contra Rorty, we cannot do everything—and more—with the Wittgensteinian notion of language-game that the pragmatists were trying to do with experience.
Vincent Colapietro (2010, p. 20)
Abstract
Robert Brandom holds that what we mean is best understood in terms of what inferences we are prepared to defend, and that such a defence is best understood in terms of rule-governed social interactions. This manages to explain quite a lot. However, for those who think that there is more to making correct/incorrect inferences than obeying/breaking accepted rules, Brandom’s account fails to adequately capture what it means to reason properly. Thus, in an effort to sketch an alternative that does not rely primarily on peer pressure, I draw on the work of C. S. Peirce. Peirce argued that, when we reason, we manipulate abstract diagrams in order to observe what results. Since some manipulations are barred by the self-same nature of the diagrams, I try to show that this qualitative incompatibility, which I dub “contrapiction,” is a good (non-social) reason to regard some reasoning as bad.
Similar content being viewed by others
References
Aristotle (1984). In Barnes, J. (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle (2 Vols). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Brandom, R. B. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brandom, R. B. (1995). Knowledge and the social articulation of the space of reasons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55(4), 895–908.
Brandom, R. B. (2000). Articulating reasons: An introduction to inferentialism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brandom, R. B. (2008). Between saying and doing: Toward an analytic pragmatism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brandom, R. B. (2009). Reason in philosophy: Animating ideas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brandom, R. B. (2011). Perspectives on pragmatism: Classical, recent, and contemporary. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brandom, R. B. (2015). From empiricism to expressivism: Brandom reads sellars. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Broome, J. (2007). Is rationality normative? Disputatio, 2(23), 161–178.
Burch, R. W. (1994). Game-theoretical semantics for Peirce’s existential graphs. Synthese, 99(3), 361–375.
Champagne, M. (2014a). Just do it: Schopenhauer and Peirce on the immediacy of agency. Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy, 18(2), 209–232.
Champagne, M. (2014b). Referring to the qualitative dimension of consciousness: Iconicity instead of indexicality. Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, 53(1), 135–182.
Champagne, M. (2014c). Semiotics. Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy. doi:10.1093/OBO/9780195396577-0179.
Champagne, M. (2015a). Disjunctivism and the ethics of disbelief. Philosophical Papers, 44(2), 139–163.
Champagne, M. (2015b). Experience and life as ever-present constraints on knowledge. Metaphilosophy, 46(2), 235–245.
Champagne, M. (2015c). Poinsot versus Peirce on merging with reality by sharing a quality. Versus, 120, 31–43.
Champagne, M. (2015d). Sound reasoning (literally): Prospects and challenges of current acoustic logics. Logica Universalis, 9(3), 331–343.
Chevalier, J.-M. (2014). Why ought we to be logical? Peirce’s naturalism on norms and rational requirements. In J. Dutant, D. Fassio, & A. Meylan (Eds.), Liber Amicorum Pascal Engel (pp. 716–740). Geneva: Université de Genève.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. J. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.
Colapietro, V. M. (2010). Peirce today. Pragmatism Today, 1(2), 7–24.
Coltheart, M. (1980). Iconic memory and visible persistence. Perception and Psychophysics, 27(3), 183–228.
Fodor, J. A., & Lepore, E. (1992). Holism: A shopper’s guide. Oxford: Blackwell.
Gillies, D. (2009). Problem-solving and the problem of induction. In Z. Parusniková & R. S. Cohen (Eds.), Rethinking Popper (pp. 103–115). Dordrecht: Springer.
Ketner, K. L. (1981). The best example of semiosis and its use in teaching semiotics. The American Journal of Semiotics, 1(1–2), 47–83.
Lance, M. (2000). The word made flesh: Toward a neo-sellarsian view of concepts, analysis, and understanding. Acta Analytica, 15(25), 117–135.
Legg, C. (2008). The problem of the essential icon. American Philosophical Quarterly, 45(3), 207–232.
Lumer, C. (1988). The disputation—a special type of cooperative argumentative dialogue. Argumentation, 2(4), 441–464.
Maher, C. (2012). The Pittsburgh school of philosophy: Sellars, McDowell, Brandom. New York: Routledge.
McDowell, J. H. (2002). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
McDowell, J. H. (2009). The engaged intellect: Philosophical essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Misak, C. (2013). The American pragmatists. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Morris, C. W. (1971). Writings on the general theory of signs. The Hague: Mouton.
Norman, A. P. (2001). The normative structure of adjudicative dialogue. Argumentation, 15(4), 489–498.
Paavola, S. (2011). Diagrams, iconicity, and abductive discovery. Semiotica, 186(1–4), 297–314.
Peirce, C. S. (1931–1958). The collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (Vols. 1–6 edited by C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss, Vols. 7–8 edited by A. W. Burks). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1982). In Fisch, M. H. (Ed.), The writings of Charles S. Peirce: A chronological edition (Vol. 1). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1992). In Houser, N., et al. (Eds.), The essential Peirce (Vol. 1). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1998). In Houser, N., et al. (Eds.), The essential Peirce (Vol. 2). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (2015a). In Pietarinen, A.-V. (Ed.), Logic of the future: Peirce’s writings on existential graphs. Bloomington: Indiana University Press (in press).
Peirce, C. S. (2015b). Two papers on existential graphs by Charles Peirce. Edited by Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen. Synthese, 192(4), 881–922.
Peregrin, J. (2001). Meaning and structure. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Pietarinen, A.-V. (2006). Signs of logic: Peircean themes on the philosophy of language, games, and communication. Dordrecht: Springer.
Pietarinen, A.-V. (2007). Getting closer to iconic logic. In G. D. Crnkovic & A. J. Stuart (Eds.), Computing, philosophy, and cognitive science: The nexus and the liminal (pp. 53–74). Cambridge: Newcastle upon Tyne.
Pietarinen, A.-V. (2011). Existential graphs: What a diagrammatic logic of cognition might look like. History and Philosophy of Logic, 32(3), 265–281.
Psillos, S. (2011). An explorer upon untrodden ground: Peirce on abduction. In D. Gabbay, S. Hartmann, & J. Woods (Eds.), Handbook of the history of logic, vol. 10: Inductive logic (pp. 117–151). Oxford: Elsevier.
Rescher, N. (1987). How serious a fallacy is inconsistency? Argumentation, 1(3), 303–316.
Roberts, D. D. (1973). The existential graphs of Charles S. Peirce. The Hague: Mouton.
Rorty, R. M. (1982). Consequences of pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Sebeok, T. A. (1981). The play of musement. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 1, pp. 253–329). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Sellars, W. ([1963] 1991). Science, perception, and reality. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.
Sellars, W. ([1968] 1992). Science and metaphysics: Variations on Kantian themes. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.
Shimojima, A. (1996). On the efficacy of representation. Doctoral dissertation, Indiana University.
Shin, S.-J. (2002). The iconic logic of Peirce’s graphs. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Sowa, J. F. (2011). Peirce’s tutorial on existential graphs. Semiotica, 186(1–4), 347–394.
Stjernfelt, F. (2000). Diagrams as centerpiece in a Peircean epistemology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 36(3), 357–392.
Stjernfelt, F. (2007). Diagrammatology: An investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Dordrecht: Springer.
Stjernfelt, F. (2014a). Diagrams, narratives and ‘reality’. Sign Systems Studies, 42(2–3), 412–416.
Stjernfelt, F. (2014b). Natural propositions: The actuality of Peirce’s doctrine of dicisigns. Boston: Docent Press.
Wanderer, J. (2008). Robert Brandom. Durham, UK: Acumen.
White, H. (2003). Brandom on practical reason. The Philosophical Quarterly, 23(213), 566–572.
Williams, J. J. (2013). Inferential man: An interview with Robert Brandom. Symploke, 21(1–2), 373–397.
Wittgenstein, L. ([1921] 1974). Tractatus logico-philosophicus (D. F. Pears & B. F. McGuinness, Trans.). London and New York: Routledge.
Wittgenstein, L. ([1953] 2001). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.
Acknowledgments
I want to thank Robert Brandom, Henry Jackman, Erkki Kilpinen, Henrik Rydenfelt, Frederik Stjernfelt, James Burton, Francesco Bellucci, anonymous reviewers for this journal, as well as audience members at the Helsinki Metaphysical Club and the 2015 CLMPS symposium on “Tracking the Diagrammatic Turn in Recent Philosophy of Notation.” This work was conducted as part of the research project Diagrammatic Mind: Logical and Cognitive Aspects of Iconicity, funded by the Academy of Finland and the Estonian Research Council. I am especially indebted to that project’s principal investigator, Prof. Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, for his continued friendship and support.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Champagne, M. Brandom, Peirce, and the overlooked friction of contrapiction. Synthese 193, 2561–2576 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0866-2
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0866-2