Abstract
There have been recent disagreements in the philosophy of neuroscience regarding which sorts of scientific models provide mechanistic explanations, and which do not (e.g. computational models, dynamical models, topological models). These disagreements often hinge on two commonly adopted, but conflicting, ways of understanding mechanistic explanations: what I call the “representation-as” account, and the “representation-of” account. In this paper, I argue that neither account does justice to neuroscientific practice. In their place, I offer a new alternative that can defuse some of these disagreements. I argue that individual models do not provide mechanistic explanations by themselves (regardless of what type of model they are). Instead, individual models are always used to complement a huge body of background information and pre-existing models about the target system. With this in mind, I argue that mechanistic explanations are distributed across sets of different, and sometimes contradictory, scientific models. Each of these models contributes limited, but essential, information to the same mechanistic explanation, but none can be considered a mechanistic explanation in isolation of the others.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
Carandini and Heeger (2012) define CNCs as “standard computational modules that apply the same fundamental operations in a variety of contexts” (p. 51).
This is arguably still consistent with Kaplan’s claim that the 3M requirement is intended as a tool to help “guide the direction of theoretical inquiry” (2011, p. 347).
Eliasmith, for instances, explicitly argues that most kinds of statistical, dynamical, and computational models fail to provide mechanistic explanations on these grounds (2010).
Another historical example is the study of the mechanism for protein synthesis. The mechanism for protein synthesis was not explained by any single representation, but by the piecemeal collection of various different models generated within different fields (Machamer et al. 2000, pp. 18–21).
I would like to offer special thanks to a blind referee for highlighting this worry.
References
Aldrich, R., Corey, D., & Stevens, C. (1984). A reinterpretation of mammalian sodium channel gating based on single channel recording. Nature, 308, 436–441.
Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. New York: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Bechtel, W. (2009). Looking down, around, and up: Mechanistic explanation in psychology. Philosophical Psychology, 22(5), 543–564.
Bechtel, W. (2015). Can mechanistic explanation be reconciled with scale-free constitution and dynamics? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences. doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2015.03.006.
Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanistic alternative. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.
Carandini, M., & Heeger, D. J. (1994). Summation and division by neurons in primate visual cortex. Science, 264, 1333–1336.
Carandini, M., & Heeger, D. J. (2012). Normalization as a canonical neural computation. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 13, 51–62.
Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). After the philosophy of mind: Replacing scholasticism with science. Philosophy of Science, 75, 1–27.
Chirimuuta, M. (2014). Minimal models and canonical neural computations: The distinctness of computational explanation in neuroscience. Synthese, 191(2), 127–154.
Colombo, M., Hartmann, S., & van Iersel, R. (2015). Models, mechanisms, and coherence. The British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 66, 181–212.
Craver, C. (2006). When mechanistic models explain. Synthese, 153(3), 355–376.
Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Craver, C. (2009). Mechanisms and natural kinds. Philosophical Psychology, 22(5), 575–594.
Craver, C. (2014). The ontic account of scientific explanation. In M. I. Kaiser, et al. (Eds.), Explanation in the special sciences: The case of biology and history, synthese library (pp. 27–52). New York: Springer.
Craver, C. (2015). Graphing the Brain’s dark energy: Network analysis in the search for neural mechanisms. Paper presented at annual meeting of the International Society for the History, Philosophy, and Social Studies in Biology. Montreal, QC, Canada.
Craver, C. (Under Review). Network models and explanations.
Craver, C., & Bechtel, W. (2006). Mechanism. In S. Sarkar & J. Pfeifer (Eds.), Philosophy of science: An encyclopedia. New York: Routledge.
Eliasmith, C. (2002). The myth of the turing machine: The failing of functionalism and related theses. Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 14(1), 1–8.
Eliasmith, C. (2010). How we ought to describe computation in the brain. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41, 313–320.
Eliasmith, C. (2013). How to build a brain: A neural architecture for biological cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Eliasmith, C., & Trujillo, O. (2014). The use and abuse of large-scale brain models. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 25, 1–6.
Heeger, D. J. (1992). Normalization of cell responses in the cat striate cortex. Visual Neuroscience, 9, 181–197.
Hille, B. (1984). Ionic channels of excitable membranes. Sutherland, MA: Sinauer.
Hochstein, E. (2012). Minds, models, and mechanisms: A new perspective on intentional psychology. Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 24(4), 547–557.
Hochstein, E. (2013). Intentional models as essential scientific tools. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 27(2), 199–217.
Hodgkin, A. L., & Huxley, A. F. (1952). A quantitative description of membrane current and its application to conduction and excitation in nerve. Journal of Physiology, 117, 500–44.
Huneman, P. (2010). Topological explanations and robustness in biological sciences. Synthese, 177(2), 213–245.
Jones, N. (2014). Bowtie structures, pathway diagrams, and topological explanation. Erkenntnis, 79(5), 1135–1155.
Kandel, E. R., Schwartz, J. H., & Jessell, T. M. (1991). Principles of neural science (3rd ed.). New York: Elsevier.
Kaplan, D. M. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183, 339–373.
Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. F. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical and mathematical models in neuroscience: A mechanistic perspective. Philosophy of Science, 78, 601–627.
Keeley, B. (2000). Shocking lessons from electric fish: The theory and practice of multiple realizability. Philosophy of Science, 67, 444–465.
Le Cun, Y., & Denker J. S. (1992). Natural versus universal probability, complexity, and entropy. IEEE Workshop on the Physics of Computation.
Levy, A., & Bechtel, W. (2013). Abstraction and the organization of mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 80(2), 241–261.
Longino, H. (2006). Theoretical pluralism and the scientific study of behavior. In S. Kellert, H. Longino, & C. K. Waters (Eds.), Scientific pluralism (pp. 102–132). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Longino, H. (2013). Studying human behavior: How scientists investigate aggression and sexuality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.
MacLeod, M., & Nersessian, N. J. (2015). Modeling systems-level dynamics: Understanding without mechanistic explanation in integrative systems biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science, 49, 1–11.
Meves, H. (1983). A new view of the sodium channel. In “News and Views,”. Nature, 306, 425.
Milkowski, M. (2011). Beyond formal structure: A mechanistic perspective on computation and implementation. Journal of Cognitive Science, 12(4), 359–379.
Milkowski, M. (2013). A mechanistic account of computational explanation in cognitive science. In Proceedings of the annual meeting of the Cognitive Science Society.
Piccinini, G. (2006). Computational explanation and mechanistic explanation of mind. In M. DeCaro, F. Ferretti, & M. Marraffa (Eds.), C artographies of the mind: The interface between philosophy and cognitive science. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Piccinini, G. (2007). Computing mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 74(4), 501–526.
Piccinini, G. (2008). Computers. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 89(1), 32–73.
Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical computation: A mechanist account. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183, 283–311.
Potochnik, A. (unpublished). Idealization and the aims of science.
Povich, M. (forthcoming). Mechanisms and model-based fMRI. Philosophy of Science.
Raerinne, J. (2011). Causal and mechanistic explanations in ecology. Acta Biotheoretica, 59, 251–271.
Ross, L. (2015). Dynamical models and explanation in neuroscience. Philosophy of Science, 82(1), 32–54.
Ruch, T., & Fulton, J. (1960). Medical physiology and biophysics (18th ed.). Philadelphia: Saunders.
Rusanen, A. M., & Lappi, O. (2007). The limits of mechanistic explanation in neurocognitive sciences. In Proceedings of the European cognitive science conference.
Sejnowski, T. J., Churchland, P. S., & Koch, C. (1988). Computational neuroscience. Science, 241, 1299–1306.
Shapiro, L. A. (2004). The mind incarnate. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Shagrir, O. (2006). Why we view the brain as a computer. Synthese, 153(3), 393–416.
Shagrir, O. (2010). Brains as analog-model computers. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 41(3), 271–279.
Singer, S. J., & Nicolson, G. L. (1972). The fluid mosaic model of the structure of cell membranes. Science, 175(4023), 720–731.
Stepp, N., Chemero, A., & Turvey, M. (2011). Philosophy for the rest of cognitive science. Topics in Cognitive Science, 3(2), 425–437.
Syropoulos, A. (2008). Hypercomputation: Computing beyond the church-turing barrier. New York: Springer.
Thelen, E., & Smith, B. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Trumpler, M. (1997). Techniques of intervention and forms of representation of sodium-channel proteins in nerve cell membranes. Journal of History of Biology, 30(1), 55–89.
Van Gelder, T., & Port, R. (1995). It’s about time: An overview of the dynamical approach to cognition. In R. Port & T. Van Gelder (Eds.), Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition (pp. 1–43). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Walmsley, J. (2008). Explanation in dynamical cognitive science. Minds and Machines, 18(3), 331–348.
Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. Journal of Philosophy, 104(12), 639–659.
Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. New York: Oxford University Press.
Woodward, J. (2002). What is a mechanism? A counterfactual account. Philosophy of Science, 69, 366–S377.
Zednik, C. (2011). The nature of dynamical explanation. Philosophy of Science, 78(2), 238–263.
Acknowledgments
I would like to offer my thanks to the Centre for Theoretical Neuroscience at the University of Waterloo, and the PNP Work in Progress Seminar at Washington University in St Louis, for feedback and advice on earlier drafts of this paper. Special thanks go to Carl Craver, Gualtiero Piccinini, Doreen Fraser, Anya Plutynski, Kate Shrumm, Mark Povich, Kurt Holukoff, and Robyn Holukoff, for helpful suggestions and guidance in shaping this paper. This research was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada Postdoctoral Award.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflicts of interest
The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.
Funding
This paper was funded by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (award number: 756-2013-0215).
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Hochstein, E. One mechanism, many models: a distributed theory of mechanistic explanation. Synthese 193, 1387–1407 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0844-8
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0844-8