Abstract
According to Ian Hacking’s Entity Realism, unobservable entities that scientists carefully manipulate to study other phenomena are real. Although Hacking presents his case in an intuitive, attractive, and persuasive way, his argument remains elusive. I present five possible readings of Hacking’s argument: a no-miracle argument, an indispensability argument, a transcendental argument, a Vichian argument, and a non-argument. I elucidate Hacking’s argument according to each reading, and review their strengths, their weaknesses, and their compatibility with each other.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
My subsequent mentions of truth should be understood as referring to approximate truth as well.
I thank Anjan Chakravartty and an anonymous reviewer for this clarification.
This is not to deny that an IBE may have a double warrant. I discuss this option in Sect. 5.
According to my taxonomy of argument types, Morrison’s interpretation can also be read as an indispensability interpretation.
In fact, it is hard to interpret Maddy’s (2007, p. 406) own explication and analysis of Perrin’s argument for the existence of atoms other than as an IBE. Even according to Maddy’s own account, Perrin inferred the existence of unobservable atoms from the fact that they produced an observable pattern that was identical to the pattern of Brownian motion of observable entities, where the production of such Brownian motion by atoms had been a novel prediction of statistical thermodynamics.
I thank Yemima Ben-Menahem for drawing my attention to the resemblance between Hacking and Vico.
References
Bardon, A. (2006). Transcendental Arguments. In J. Fieser & B. Dowden (Eds.), The internet encyclopedia of philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/trans-ar/
Ben-Menahem, Y. (1990). Inference to the best explanation. Erkenntnis, 33, 319–334.
Boon, M., & Knuuttila, T. (2011). Breaking up with the epochal break: The case of engineering sciences. In A. Nordmann, H. Radder, & G. Schiemann (Eds.), Science transformed? Debating claims of an epochal break. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Brown, J. R. (1997). Proofs and pictures. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48(2), 161–180.
Carrier, M. (2011). Knowledge is power’, or how to capture the relationship between science and technoscience. In A. Nordmann, H. Radder, & G. Schiemann (Eds.), Science transformed? Debating claims of an epochal break (pp. 43–53). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Chakravartty, A. (2013). Scientific realism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scientific-realism/
Collins, H. (1985). Changing order: Replication and induction in scientific practice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Colyvan, M. (2014). Indispensability arguments in the philosophy of mathematics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mathphil-indis/
Day, T., & Kincaid, H. (1994). Putting inference to the best explanation in its place. Synthese, 98(2), 271–295.
Enoch, D. (2011). Taking morality seriously: A defense of robust realism. Oxford: OUP.
Gelfert, A. (2003). Manipulative success and the unreal. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 17(3), 245–263.
Giere, R. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Goldman, A. I. (2001). Experts: Which ones should you trust? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63(1), 85–111.
Greco, J. (2002). How to Reid Moore. The Philosophical Quarterly, 52(209), 544–563.
Grundmann, T., & Misselhorn, C. (2003). Transcendental arguments and realism. In H.-J. Glock (Ed.), Strawson and kant (pp. 205–218). Oxford: Oxford UP.
Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Hacking, I. (1988). The participant irrealist at large in the laboratory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39(3), 277–294.
Hacking, I. (1989). Extragalactic reality: The case of gravitational lensing. Philosophy of Science, 56(4), 555–581.
Hardwig, J. (1985). Epistemic dependence. The Journal of Philosophy, 82(7), 335–349.
Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Ladyman, J. (2014). Structural realism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/structural-realism/
Lehoux, D. (2012). What did the romans know? An inquiry into science and worldmaking. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lipton, P. (2003). Kant on wheels. Social Epistemology, 17(2&3), 215–219.
Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.
Lyons, T. D., & Clarke, S. (2002). Introduction: Scientific realism and commonsense. In S. Clarke & T. D. Lyons (Eds.), Scientific realism and commonsense. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Maddy, P. (2007). Second philosophy: A naturalistic method. Oxford: OUP.
Moore, G. E. (1962). Proof of an external world. In Philosophical papers (pp. 126–148). New York: Collier Books.
Morrison, M. (1990). Theory, intervention and realism. Synthese, 82(1), 1–22.
Putnam, H. (1975). Mathematics, matter and method. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Stroud, B. (1968). Transcendental arguments. The Journal of Philosophy, 65(9), 241–256.
Zagorin, P. (1984). Vico’s theory of knowledge: A critique. The Philosophical Quarterly, 34(134), 15–30.
Acknowledgments
I thank Anjan Chakravartty, Jacob Stegenga, Yemima Ben-Menahem, and Daniel Steel for helpful comments and discussions. This paper was presented at the Israel Society for History and Philosophy of Science Annual Meeting, Jerusalem, 2013, and at the PSA Biennial Meeting, Chicago, 2014. I thank the audience members for helpful comments. I am grateful to the students at my seminar in philosophy of science at the Bar Ilan University Graduate Program in Science, Technology, and Society for realizing that getting at the bottom of Hacking’s argument is tricky. I thank the Dan David Foundation, the Cohn Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Ideas, Tel Aviv University, and the Sidney M. Edelstein Center for History and Philosophy of Science, Technology and Medicine, the Hebrew University of Jerusalem, for postdoctoral fellowships.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Miller, B. What is Hacking’s argument for entity realism?. Synthese 193, 991–1006 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0789-y
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0789-y