Conceptual analysis and natural kinds: the case of knowledge | Synthese Skip to main content
Log in

Conceptual analysis and natural kinds: the case of knowledge

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is a line of reasoning in metaepistemology that is congenial to naturalism and hard to resist, yet ultimately misguided: that knowledge might be a natural kind, and that this would undermine the use of conceptual analysis in the theory of knowledge. In this paper, I first bring out various problems with Hilary Kornblith’s argument from the causal–explanatory indispensability of knowledge to the natural kindhood of knowledge. I then criticize the argument from the natural kindhood of knowledge against the method of conceptual analysis in the theory of knowledge. A natural motivation for this argument is the following seemingly plausible principle: if knowledge is a natural kind, then the concept of knowledge is a natural kind concept. Since this principle lacks adequate support, the crucial semantic claim that the concept of knowledge is a natural kind concept must be defended in some more direct way. However, there are two striking epistemic disanalogies between the concept of knowledge and paradigmatic natural kind concepts that militate against this semantic claim. Conceptual analyses of knowledge are not affected by total error, and the proponents of such analyses are not subject to a priori conceptual obliviousness. I conclude that the argument from natural kindhood does not succeed in undermining the use of conceptual analysis in the theory of knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
¥17,985 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (Japan)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Other proponents of naturalized epistemology tend to concur. For example, Victor Kumar claims: “If knowledge is a natural kind, then the satisfaction conditions for ‘knowledge’ cannot be discovered through armchair reflection of the sort that is characteristic of traditional conceptual analysis.” (Kumar 2014, p. 442).

  2. I follow the usual convention of indicating reference to concepts with small caps.

  3. This qualification is supposed to rule out circular or irrelevant necessary conditions, such as the condition of being self-identical or being such that 2 \(+\) 2 \(=\) 4. In fact, I think that an adequate account of philosophical analysis requires a more substantial and specific condition than the fairly vague requirement of being illuminating (cf. Horvath, manuscript). But for our present purposes, this condition should work reasonably well.

  4. For example, in his An Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology Matthias Steup writes: “For an analysis to be correct, the analysans must specify conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient for the analysandum. [...] For an analysis to be successful, it must be illuminating [...]” (Steup 1996, pp. 27–28).

  5. Why this hedged formulation? Because the connection between a philosophical analysis and the essence of the relevant property or kind is less straightforward than is commonly assumed (cf. Horvath, manuscript). In particular, the nature of this link depends on one’s general metaphysical commitments concerning the metaphysics of properties and essences. For example, if one takes properties to be mere sets of possibilia (cf. Lewis 1986, Chap.  1.5), then all necessarily co-instantiated properties will be identical, and thus a necessary biconditional that states necessary and sufficient conditions for X will effectively just tell us that a certain property X—which can be expressed in at least two different ways—is necessarily self-co-instantiated. However, such general truths about properties arguably do not belong to the essence of any particular property, and thus the necessary biconditional in question would not reveal the specific nature of the property of being X (cf. Fine 1995). In this case, an analysis of X would be more like an informative identity claim, such as ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’, than like a claim about the essence of being X—because being the set of all possible Xs might already exhaust the latter.

  6. I use the terms ‘essence’ and ‘nature’ interchangeably in this paper.

  7. I indicate reference to properties or kinds with italics, and I will mostly gloss over the difference, if any, between properties and kinds (unless explicitly noted otherwise).

  8. The account is mainly developed in Kornblith (1993), and it is basically a version of Richard Boyd’s account of natural kinds (cf. Boyd 1988, 1991).

  9. One might object that conceptual analysis could also pursue the weaker goal of providing a cluster analysis, e.g., in the sense of Searle (1969, Chap. 7), which would seem to be compatible with the homeostatic cluster account of natural kinds (thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue). The basic idea is that something only needs to satisfy sufficiently many (but not all) of the analyzing features that a cluster analysis of some category K specifies in order to qualify as an instance of K. From a methodological point of view, however, this can only be seen as a highly revisionary proposal, at least with respect to the category of knowledge—it certainly does not reflect how most epistemologists conceive of their own attempts at analyzing knowledge.

  10. In fact, Kornblith explicitly endorses the basic contours of the Putnam–Kripke conception of natural kinds and natural kind concepts (Kornblith 2002, pp. 12–13, fn. 17 & 18).

  11. Note that the converse argument from ‘knowledge is a natural kind concept’ to ‘knowledge is a natural kind’ clearly fails, because a natural kind concept may fail to pick out any kind at all, as in the case of phlogiston, or it may pick out a disjunctive, non-natural kind, as in the case of jade. One might object that it is not clear what exactly makes phlogiston or jade a natural kind concept in the first place, given that they actually fail to pick out a natural kind (thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue). First, of course, what makes them natural kind concepts is the fact that they are equally nondescriptive as paradigmatic natural kind concepts, such as mass or gold. But since nondescriptiveness is not sufficient for being a natural kind concept—given that one can even refer to a non-natural kind like bachelorhood with a nondescriptive concept (see below in the main text)—there must be some further reason why it is legitimate to regard phlogiston and jade as natural kind concepts. A plausible suggestion would be that the way the concepts phlogiston and jade were introduced is completely analogous to the way certain paradigmatic natural kind concepts were introduced, and this, together with their nondescriptiveness, suffices to regard them as natural kind concepts. With some amount of idealization, we can say that, for example, the concept phlogiston was introduced to refer to a certain natural phenomenon that was (incorrectly) thought to play a particular theoretical role in chemistry—just like the concept mass was introduced to refer to a certain natural phenomenon that was (correctly) thought to play a particular theoretical role in physics. And again with some amount of idealization, we can say that the concept jade was introduced by ostension to particular instances of jade, with the (unsuccessful) intention of referring to that kind of stuff or natural kind (depending on the conceptual sophistication of those who introduced the concept)—just like the concept gold was introduced by ostension to particular instances of gold, with the (successful) intention of referring to that kind of stuff or natural kind (see also Soames 2007).

  12. According to some accounts of natural kind concepts, they must at least have a minimal descriptive core in order to solve the so-called ‘qua-problem’ (see, e.g., Devitt and Sterelny 1999). For example, one might try to fix the reference of the concept tiger to the natural kind tiger by ostension to actual tigers, which is one important way to fix the reference of natural kind concepts. But then it may still be indeterminate whether tiger refers to tigers, animals, living beings, or material objects. For this reason, natural kind concepts may need a certain minimum of descriptive features in their content, such as being an animal. As a consequence, one may come to know certain trivial facts about tigers merely on the basis of analyzing the concept tiger, e.g., that tigers are animals. This is still a far cry from illuminating necessary and sufficient conditions for being a tiger, however.

  13. Natural kind concepts are also standardly regarded as rigid designators (cf. Kripke 1980), i.e., as concepts that have the same referent in all possible worlds (where they have a referent at all). However, it is an open question whether the notion of rigidity—which was primarily developed for singular terms—can also be extended to general terms or general concepts, like water, gold, or bachelor (cf. Besson 2010; Schwartz 1980, 2002; Soames 2002, Chap. 9). For example, if one identifies the reference of general concepts with their extension, then the reference of most natural kind concepts will clearly not be the same in all relevant possible worlds. There surely could have been, e.g., more or less water or gold than there actually is, so the extension of water and gold changes across possible worlds. What if one identifies the reference of general concepts with the relevant property or kind instead, e.g., with the property of being gold in case of the concept gold? This assigns a reference to gold that does indeed remain constant across all relevant possible worlds. But the same holds for general concepts that are clearly not natural kind concepts. For example, if the concept bachelor has the property of being a bachelor as its referent, then it surely refers to that property in all possible worlds where it has a referent at all—for, which other property should it refer to if not to the property being a bachelor? For these reasons, I put the issue of rigidity aside in this paper. The whole work in an argument against conceptual analysis is done by the nondescriptiveness of natural kind concepts anyway.

  14. It should be noted, however, that the natural kindhood of biological species is a highly controversial issue in contemporary philosophy of biology (cf. Bird and Tobin 2015, Sect. 2.1). In particular, it is not clear whether the nature of biological species can be understood in terms of their intrinsic, microstructural properties—or whether it must instead be understood in extrinsic, relational terms (cf. Okasha 2002; LaPorte 2004).

  15. For the multiple realizability of knowledge it does not matter whether knowledge is a composite state that consists of a belief that satisfies various further conditions, such as justification or truth—which is the orthodox view in epistemology (cf. Nagel 2013)—, or whether knowledge is a distinctive mental state in its own right (cf. Williamson 1995, 2000; Nagel 2013).

  16. The apparent analyzability of fragility should not be confused with the seemingly more problematic idea of providing illuminating necessary and sufficient conditions for the dispositionality of fragility (cf. Bird 2007; Ellis 2001; Mumford 2004).

  17. Thanks to Brendan Balcerak Jackson for discussion.

  18. According to a competing hypothesis, the prime life cycles of Magicicada are adaptations that prevent hybridization in small and isolated populations (cf. Cox and Carlton 1988; Yoshimura 1997).

  19. We are only considering a special science explanation here, of course, just as Kornblith does in the case of knowledge and cognitive ethology.

  20. Thanks to Kirk Michaelian for pressing this point.

  21. A proposed analysis \(\hbox {A}_{\mathrm{p}}\) of K is subject to total error iff none of the analyzing features that figure in \(\hbox {A}_{\mathrm{p}}\) also figure in the correct analysis \(\hbox {A}_{\mathrm{c}}\) of K.

  22. A thinker T is subject to a priori conceptual obliviousness with respect to the correct analysis \(\hbox {A}_\mathrm{c}\) of K iff T possesses none (or almost none) of the concepts \(\hbox {C}_\mathrm{1}\), ..., \(\hbox {C}_\mathrm{n}\) that are needed for grasping the analyzing features that figure in \(\hbox {A}_\mathrm{c}\), and there is no realistic way for T to acquire \(\hbox {C}_\mathrm{1}\), ..., \(\hbox {C}_\mathrm{n}\) solely through further a priori theorizing.

References

  • Armstrong, D. (1968). A materialist theory of the mind. London: Routledge & K. Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Besson, C. (2010). Rigidity, natural kind terms and metasemantics. In H. Beebee & N. Sabbarton-Leary (Eds.), The semantics and metaphysics of natural kind terms. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2013). Multiple Realizability. In E. N. Zalta (Eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved March 5, 2015, from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/multiple-realizability/.

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A., & Tobin, E. (2015). Natural kinds. In E. N. Zalta (Eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved February 27, 2015, from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/natural-kinds/.

  • Boyd, R. (1988). How to be a moral realist. In G. Sayre McCord (Ed.), Essays on moral realism. Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1991). Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61(1), 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Jackson, F. (2007). The philosophy of mind and cognition: An introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4, 73–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Winblad, D. (1999). Intuitions. Facta Philosophica, 1, 197–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox, R. T., & Carlton, C. E. (1988). Paleoclimatic influences in the evolution of periodical cicadas (Insecta: Homoptera: Cicadidae: Magicicada spp.). American Midland Naturalist, 120(1), 183–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M., & Sterelny, K. (1999). Language and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1995). Senses of essence. In R. B. Marcus, W. Sinnott-Armstrong, D. Raffman, & N. Asher (Eds.), Modality, morality and belief: Essays in honour of Ruth Barcan Marcus (pp. 53–73). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1974). Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28(2), 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23(6), 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge (pp. 1–23). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2007). Philosophical intuitions: Their target, their source, and their epistemic status. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 74, 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goles, E., Schulz, O., & Markus, M. (2001). Prime number selection of cycles in a predator-prey model. Complexity, 6(4), 33–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. (1996). The mad scientist meets the robot cats: Compatibilism, kinds, and counterexamples. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56(2), 333–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, J. (2011). In defense of conceptual analysis. Dissertation. University of Cologne.

  • Horvath, J. (manuscript). Philosophical analysis: The concept grounding view.

  • Ichikawa, J. J., & Steup, M. (2012). The analysis of knowledge. In Edward N. Zalta (Eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved April 9, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/knowledge-analysis/.

  • Kant, I. (1977). In J. W. Ellington (Ed.), Prolegomena to any future metaphysics. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Kornblith, H. (1993). Inductive inference and its natural ground: An essay in naturalistic epistemology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (1999). Knowledge in humans and other animals. Philosophical Perspectives, 13, 327–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2002). Knowledge and its place in nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2007). Naturalism and intuitions. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 74, 27–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2013). Is there room for armchair theorizing in epistemology? In M. Haug (Ed.), Philosophical methodology: The armchair or the laboratory? (pp. 195–216). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumar, V. (2014). ‘Knowledge’ as a natural kind term. Synthese, 191(3), 439–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LaPorte, J. (2004). Natural kinds and conceptual change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K., & Paxson, T. (1969). Knowledge: Undefeated justified true belief. Journal of Philosophy, 66(8), 225–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1972). Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50(3), 249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, K. (2013). Methods in analytic epistemology. In M. Haug (Ed.), Philosophical methodology: The armchair or the laboratory? (pp. 217–239). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malmgren, A.-S. (2011). Rationalism and the content of intuitive judgements. Mind, 120(478), 263–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miščević, N. (2000). Deep and superficial a priori. Acta Analytica: Philosophy and Psychology, 15, 89–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miščević, N. (2005). Empirical concepts and a priori truth. Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 5, 289–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J. (2013). Knowledge as a mental state. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology (pp. 272–308). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2002). Darwinian metaphysics: Species and the question of essentialism. Synthese, 131(2), 191–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pernu, T. K. (2009). Is knowledge a natural kind? Philosophical Studies, 142(3), 371–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological predicates. In W. H. Capitan & D. D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion (pp. 37–48). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1970). Is semantics possible? Mind, language and reality?: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 139–152). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of meaning. Mind, language and reality : Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 215–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S. (1980). Formal semantics and natural kind terms. Philosophical Studies, 38(2), 189–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S. (2002). Kinds, general terms, and rigidity: A reply to LaPorte. Philosophical Studies, 109(3), 265–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). Against metaphysics, especially the metaphysics of consciousness. The Splintered Mind. http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com/2008/07/against-metaphysics-especially.html.

  • Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. London: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Senor, T. D. (2013). Justified belief and demon worlds. Res Philosophica, 90(2), 203–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1981). Some varieties of functionalism. Philosophical Topics, 12(1), 93–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shope, R. (1983). The analysis of knowing: A decade of research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shope, R. (2002). Conditions and analyses of knowledge. In P. Moser (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology (pp. 25–71). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity: The unfinished semantic agenda ofNaming and necessity’. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Soames, S. (2007). What are natural kinds? Philosophical Topics, 35(1), 329–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1999). How to defeat opposition to Moore. Noûs, 33, 141–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Steup, M. (1996). An introduction to contemporary epistemology. Upper Saddle River, N.J.: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1968). An analysis of factual knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, 65(6), 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1995). Is knowing a state of mind? Mind, 104(415), 533–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yoshimura, J. (1997). The evolutionary origins of periodical cicadas during ice ages. The American Naturalist, 149(1), 112–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (1994). The inescapability of Gettier problems. Philosophical Quarterly, 44(174), 65–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Brendan Balcerak Jackson, Thomas Grundmann, Frank Hofmann, Jonathan Jenkins Ichikawa, Stan Husi, Jens Kipper, Hilary Kornblith, Kirk Michaelian, Wolfgang Schwarz, Anand Vaidya, and various anonymous reviewers for numerous helpful comments on this paper and its non-identical predecessors. The paper originated from a critical comment on Hilary Kornblith’s work at the 2nd Cologne Summer School in Philosophy in August 2007 at the University of Cologne. Special thanks to Hilary for extensive discussion and plenty of encouragement. I also want to thank the participants of Hilary’s doctoral colloquium at the University of Massachusetts Amherst in March 2008—Kristoffer Ahlstrom-Vij, Jeremy Cushing, Jeff Dunn, Meghan Masto, Alex Sarch, Kirk Michaelian, Indrani Bhattacharjee, and Hilary Kornblith—for their generous engagement with my paper and very valuable comments. Thanks also to Brendan Balcerak Jackson, Magdalena Balcerak Jackson, Alma Barner and Wolfgang Schwarz for their very helpful comments in a reading group session of the Emmy Noether Independent Junior Research Group Understanding and the A Priori in June 2009, which was kindly hosted by the University of Cologne and generously supported by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft DFG (German Research Foundation). Additional thanks to the DFG for supporting my research on this paper as part of the project Eine Verteidigung der Begriffsanalyse gegen die Herausforderungen des Naturalismus (A Defense of Conceptual Analysis against the Challenges from Naturalism), which was kindly hosted by the University of Cologne from 2007 to 2010 (under the auspices of Thomas Grundmann).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joachim Horvath.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Horvath, J. Conceptual analysis and natural kinds: the case of knowledge. Synthese 193, 167–184 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0751-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0751-z

Keywords

Navigation