Abstract
Whether mental properties are identical with neural properties is one of the central questions of contemporary philosophy of mind. Many philosophers agree that even if mental properties are identical with neural properties, the mind-brain identity thesis cannot be established on empirical grounds, but only be vindicated by theoretical philosophical considerations. In his paper ‘When Is a Brain Like the Planet?’, Clark Glymour proposes a causal criterion for local property identifications and claims that this criterion can be used to empirically establish local identities between mental and neural properties. If successful, such an account would settle the debate on the mind-body problem. In this paper, I argue that Glymour’s approach falls short of its aims. The causal criterion which he proposes does not provide a sufficient condition for the local identification of properties. Moreover, his account does not succeed in rendering local mind-brain identities empirically testable. Therefore, the mind-body problem cannot be solved as easily as Glymour assumes.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
In Kripkean metaphysics, it is metaphysically necessary that gold is the element with the atomic number 79 (Kripke 1972, pp. 123–125). The crucial point in the present context is, however, that if the laws of nature were different, gold (that is, the element with the atomic number 79) could have a density different from 19.3 g/cm\(^{3}\).
It should be noted that if the property of having negative elementary charge was considered rather than the property ofbeing negatively charged, the argument might become problematic. For if electrons are defined as exactly those particles that have negative elementary charge, it is controversial whether or not being an electron and having negative elementary charge are distinct properties. However, the property of being negatively charged, which can be instantiated by various kinds of things other than electrons (such as iron filings or copper wires), is not even locally identical with being an electron.
For instance, there is a strong intuition to the effect that the properties of being a closed straight-sided figure having three sides and being a closed straight-sided figure having three angles are distinct. But these properties have to be classified as identical by the necessary coextensiveness criterion, since it is not possible that something is a closed straight-sided figure having three sides without being a closed straight-sided figure having three angles or vice versa (Sober 1982). This counterexample is controversial, however, because it is not clear whether mathematical properties count as appropriate test cases for criteria of property individuation.
I owe this objection to an anonymous referee.
This problem is structurally akin to the classical problem of trying to refute ceteris paribus laws: whenever a putative counterinstance is found, the law can be immunized against refutation by arguing that this particular counterinstance is excluded by the ceteris paribus condition. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pointing this out.
References
Bechtel, W. P., & McCauley, R. N. (1999). Heuristic identity theory (or back to the future): The mind-body problem against the background of research strategies in cognitive neuroscience. In M. Hahn & S. C. Stoness (Eds.), Proceedings of the 21st annual meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 67–72). Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Bechtel, W. P., & Mundale, J. (1999). Multiple realizability revisited: Linking cognitive and neural states. Philosophy of Science, 66(2), 175–207.
Block, N., & Stalnaker, R. (1999). Conceptual analysis, dualism, and the explanatory gap. Philosophical Review, 108(1), 1–46.
Glymour, C. (1999). A mind is a terrible thing to waste: Review of Mind in a Physical World by Jaegwon Kim. Philosophy of Science, 66(3), 455–471.
Glymour, C. (2004). Review of James Woodward: Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55(4), 779–790.
Glymour, C. (2007). When is a brain like the planet? Philosophy of Science, 74(3), 330–347.
Glymour, C., Danks, D., Glymour, B., Eberhardt, F., Ramsey, J., Scheines, R., et al. (2010). Actual causation: A stone soup essay. Synthese, 175, 169–192.
Hill, C. S. (1991). Sensations: A defense of type materialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hüttemann, A., Kühn, R., & Terzidis, O. (2014). Stability, emergence and part-whole-reduction. In B. Falkenburg & M. Morrison (Eds.), Why more is different: Philosophical issues in condensed matter physics and complex systems. Berlin: Springer.
Kim, J. (1989). The myth of non-reductive materialism. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 63(3), 31–47.
Kripke, S. A. (1972). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Lewis, D. (1966). An argument for the identity theory. Journal of Philosophy, 63(1), 17–25.
Lewis, D. (1980). Mad pain and martian pain. In N. Block (Ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 216–222). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
McLaughlin, B. P. (2001). In defense of new wave materialism: A response to Horgan and Tienson. In C. Gillett & B. M. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 319–330). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Molnar, G. (2003). Powers: A study in metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Polger, T. W. (2009). Evaluating the evidence for multiple realization. Synthese, 167(3), 457–472.
Polger, T. W. (2011). Are sensations still brain processes? Philosophical Psychology, 24(1), 1–21.
Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological predicates. In W. H. Capitan & D. D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion (pp. 37–48). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Shapiro, L. A. (2008). How to test for multiple realization. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 514–525.
Shapiro, L., & Sober, E. (2007). Epiphenomenalism—The do’s and the don’ts. In G. Wolters & P. Machamer (Eds.), Thinking about causes: From Greek philosophy to modern physics (pp. 235–264). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Shoemaker, S. (1988). On what there are. Philosophical Topics, 16(1), 201–223.
Smart, J. J. C. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68(2), 141–156.
Sober, E. (1982). Why logically equivalent predicates may pick out different properties. American Philosophical Quarterly, 19, 183–189.
Spirtes, P., & Scheines, R. (2004). Causal inference of ambiguous manipulations. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 833–845.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Hoffmann-Kolss, V. Of brains and planets: on a causal criterion for mind-brain identities. Synthese 193, 1177–1189 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0671-y
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0671-y