Abstract
Coherence is the property of propositions hanging or fitting together. Intuitively, adding a proposition to a set of propositions should be compatible with either increasing or decreasing the set’s degree of coherence. In this paper we show that probabilistic coherence measures based on relative overlap are in conflict with this intuitive verdict. More precisely, we prove that (i) according to the naive overlap measure it is impossible to increase a set’s degree of coherence by adding propositions and that (ii) according to the refined overlap measure no set’s degree of coherence exceeds the degree of coherence of its maximally coherent subset. We also show that this result carries over to all other subset-sensitive refinements of the naive overlap measure. As both results stand in sharp contrast to elementary coherence intuitions, we conclude that extant relative overlap measures of coherence are inadequate.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
This restriction has been called “Rescher’s principle” (Olsson 2005, p. 17) and basically amounts to the fact that coherence is a property that propositions cannot have in isolation but only in groups of at least two propositions (cf. Rescher 1973, p. 32). For exceptions to Rescher’s principle in discussions on probabilistic coherence measures see Akiba’s (2000) and Fitelson’s (2003) discussions on self-coherence.
Probabilistic measures of coherence have been discussed critically by Bovens and Hartmann (2003), Moretti and Akiba (2007), Olsson (2005), Olsson and Schubert (2007), Siebel (2005) and Siebel and Wolff (2008). For an overview of the measures and their structural properties see Schippers (2014a, b, 2015), for an overview of their performance in a collection of test cases see Koscholke (2015). The relative overlap measure has received special attention in the literature due to its high degree of truth-conduciveness as shown by Angere (2007, 2008) and its strong performance in inferences to the best explanation as presented by Glass (2012).
Nonetheless, it is worth noticing that \(\mathcal{O}'\) has some flaws in the Tweety case. What if we had not received the information about Tweety being a penguin, i.e. \(x_3\), but rather \(\lnot x_3\), i.e. the information that Tweety is not a penguin? This proposition does not establish any inferential connections to \(x_1\) or \(x_2\). Instead, it seems even to decrease coherence because given \(\lnot x_3\), one possible explanation for why \(x_1\) and \(x_2\) might be the case, our last resort of making sense of \(x_1\) and \(x_2\) in some sense, vanishes. Hence, the extended set \(\{x_1,x_2,\lnot x_3\}\) should be less coherent than \(\{x_1,x_2\}\). Quite surprisingly, the Glass–Olsson naive overlap measure satisfies this intuition since \(\mathscr {O}(\{x_1,x_2,\lnot x_3\})=0\). Meijs’ refined measure does not because \(\mathscr {O}'(\{x_1,x_2,\lnot x_3\})= 0.247\). However, one should be careful with this modified case since it involves a negated proposition. Negations are known to be difficult to handle in intuitive judgements (cf. Deutsch et al. 2009).
Notice that the arguments of probabilistic coherence measures are usually not assumed to be closed under (classical) logical consequence.
References
Akiba, K. (2000). Shogenji’s probabilistic measure of coherence is incoherent. Analysis, 60, 356–359.
Angere, S. (2007). The defeasible nature of coherentist justification. Synthese, 157(3), 321–335.
Angere, S. (2008). Coherence as a heuristic. Mind, 117(465), 1–26.
BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Deutsch, R., Kordts-Freudinger, R., Gawronski, B., & Strack, F. (2009). Fast and fragile: A new look at the automaticity of negation processing. Experimental Psychology, 56(6), 434–446.
Douven, I., & Meijs, W. (2007). Measuring coherence. Synthese, 156, 405–425.
Fitelson, B. (2003). A probabilistic theory of coherence. Analysis, 63, 194–199.
Glass, D. H. (2002). Coherence, explanation, and Bayesian networks. In M. O’Neill, R. F. E. Sutcliffe, C. Ryan, M. Eaton & N. J. L. Griffith (Eds.), Artificial intelligence and cognitive science. 13th Irish conference, AICS 2002, Limerick, Ireland, September 2002 (pp 177–182). Berlin: Springer.
Glass, D. H. (2012). Inference to the best explanation: Does it track truth? Synthese, 185(3), 411–427.
Koscholke, J. (2015). Evaluating test cases for probabilistic measures of coherence. Forthcoming in Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-015-9734-1.
Meijs, W. (2006). Coherence as generalized logical equivalence. Erkenntnis, 64, 231–252.
Moretti, L., & Akiba, K. (2007). Probabilistic measures of coherence and the problem of belief individuation. Synthese, 154, 73–95.
Olsson, E. J. (2002). What is the problem of coherence and truth? The Journal of Philosophy, 94, 246–272.
Olsson, E. J. (2005). Against coherence: Truth, probability and justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Olsson, E. J., & Schubert, S. (2007). Reliability conducive measures of coherence. Synthese, 157(3), 297–308.
Rescher, N. (1973). The coherence theory of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Roche, W. (2013). Coherence and probability: A probabilistic account of coherence. In M. Araszkiewicz & J. Savelka (Eds.), Coherence: Insights from philosophy, jurisprudence and artificial intelligence (pp. 59–91). Dordrecht: Springer.
Schippers, M. (2014a). Probabilistic measures of coherence: From adequacy constraints towards pluralism. Synthese, 191(16), 3821–3845.
Schippers, M. (2014b). Structural properties of qualitative and quantitative accounts to coherence. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 7, 579–598.
Schippers, M. (2015). The grammar of Bayesian coherentism. Studia Logica, 103:955–984.
Schupbach, J. N. (2011). New hope for Shogenji’s coherence measure. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(1), 125–142.
Shimony, A. (1955). Coherence and the axioms of confirmation. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 20, 1–28.
Shogenji, T. (1999). Is coherence truth conducive? Analysis, 59, 338–345.
Siebel, M. (2005). Against probabilistic measures of coherence. Erkenntnis, 63, 335–360.
Siebel, M., & Wolff, W. (2008). Equivalent testimonies as a touchstone of coherence measures. Synthese, 161, 167–182.
Acknowledgments
We would like to thank two anonymous reviewers whose comments helped us to improve this paper. This work was supported by Grant SI 1731/1-1 to Mark Siebel from the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG) as part of the priority program “New Frameworks of Rationality” (SPP 1516).
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Koscholke, J., Schippers, M. Against relative overlap measures of coherence. Synthese 193, 2805–2814 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0887-x
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0887-x