{"status":"ok","message-type":"work","message-version":"1.0.0","message":{"indexed":{"date-parts":[[2024,7,24]],"date-time":"2024-07-24T10:36:44Z","timestamp":1721817404552},"reference-count":89,"publisher":"Springer Science and Business Media LLC","issue":"11","license":[{"start":{"date-parts":[[2020,7,12]],"date-time":"2020-07-12T00:00:00Z","timestamp":1594512000000},"content-version":"tdm","delay-in-days":0,"URL":"https:\/\/www.springer.com\/tdm"},{"start":{"date-parts":[[2020,7,12]],"date-time":"2020-07-12T00:00:00Z","timestamp":1594512000000},"content-version":"vor","delay-in-days":0,"URL":"https:\/\/www.springer.com\/tdm"}],"content-domain":{"domain":["link.springer.com"],"crossmark-restriction":false},"short-container-title":["Synthese"],"published-print":{"date-parts":[[2021,11]]},"DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-020-02750-9","type":"journal-article","created":{"date-parts":[[2020,7,12]],"date-time":"2020-07-12T13:02:25Z","timestamp":1594558945000},"page":"10733-10763","update-policy":"http:\/\/dx.doi.org\/10.1007\/springer_crossmark_policy","source":"Crossref","is-referenced-by-count":10,"title":["Anti-intellectualist motor knowledge"],"prefix":"10.1007","volume":"198","author":[{"given":"Gabriele","family":"Ferretti","sequence":"first","affiliation":[]}],"member":"297","published-online":{"date-parts":[[2020,7,12]]},"reference":[{"key":"2750_CR1","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"97","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-008-9349-z","volume":"170","author":"M Adams","year":"2009","unstructured":"Adams, M. (2009). Empirical evidence and the knowledge-that\/knowledge-how distinction. Synthese, 170, 97\u2013114.","journal-title":"Synthese"},{"issue":"6","key":"2750_CR2","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"679","DOI":"10.1016\/S0960-9822(95)00133-3","volume":"5","author":"S Aglioti","year":"1995","unstructured":"Aglioti, S., DeSouza, J. F. X., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). Size-contrast illusions deceive the eye but not the hand. Current Biology, 5(6), 679\u2013685.","journal-title":"Current Biology"},{"key":"2750_CR97","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"1325","DOI":"10.1098\/rstb.2008.0312","volume":"364","author":"LF Barrett","year":"2009","unstructured":"Barrett, L. F., & Bar, L. F. (2009). See it with feeling: Affective predictions during object perception. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 364, 1325\u20131334. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1098\/rstb.2008.0312.","journal-title":"Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society"},{"key":"2750_CR3","unstructured":"Berm\u00fadez, J., & Cahen, A. Nonconceptual mental content. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta\u00a0(ed.). https:\/\/plato.stanford.edu\/archives\/fall2015\/entries\/content-nonconceptual\/."},{"issue":"351","key":"2750_CR4","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"2015","DOI":"10.3389\/fnhum.2015.00351","volume":"9","author":"AM Borghi","year":"2015","unstructured":"Borghi, A. M., & Riggio, L. (2015). Stable and variable affordances are both automatic and flexible. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 9(351), 2015. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.3389\/fnhum.2015.00351.","journal-title":"Frontiers in Human Neuroscience"},{"issue":"7","key":"2750_CR5","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"1435","DOI":"10.1111\/cogs.12226","volume":"39","author":"R Briscoe","year":"2015","unstructured":"Briscoe, R., & Schwenkler, J. (2015). Conscious vision in action. Cognitive Science, 39(7), 1435\u20131467.","journal-title":"Cognitive Science"},{"issue":"2011","key":"2750_CR6","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"449","DOI":"10.1016\/j.concog.2010.10.002","volume":"20","author":"B Brogaard","year":"2011","unstructured":"Brogaard, B. (2011a). Are there unconscious perceptual processes? Consciousness and Cognition, 20(2011), 449\u2013463.","journal-title":"Consciousness and Cognition"},{"key":"2750_CR7","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"1076","DOI":"10.1111\/j.1551-6709.2011.01171.x","volume":"35","author":"B Brogaard","year":"2011","unstructured":"Brogaard, B. (2011b). Conscious vision for action versus unconscious vision for action? Cognitive Science, 35, 1076\u20131104.","journal-title":"Cognitive Science"},{"issue":"2","key":"2750_CR8","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"220","DOI":"10.1093\/analys\/ant003","volume":"73","author":"J Brown","year":"2013","unstructured":"Brown, J. (2013). Knowing-how: Linguistics and cognitive science. Analysis, 73(2), 220\u2013227.","journal-title":"Analysis"},{"issue":"2","key":"2750_CR9","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"242","DOI":"10.1080\/13869795.2017.1312504","volume":"20","author":"DC Burnston","year":"2017","unstructured":"Burnston, D. C. (2017). Interface problems in the explanation of action. Philosophical Explorations, 20(2), 242\u2013258.","journal-title":"Philosophical Explorations"},{"issue":"1","key":"2750_CR10","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"119","DOI":"10.1111\/j.1933-1592.2012.00604.x","volume":"88","author":"SA Butterfill","year":"2014","unstructured":"Butterfill, S. A., & Sinigaglia, C. (2014). Intention and motor representation in purposive action: Intention and motor representation in purposive action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1), 119\u2013145. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1111\/j.1933-1592.2012.00604.x.","journal-title":"Philosophy and Phenomenological Research"},{"key":"2750_CR11","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","unstructured":"Carter, J. A., & Pritchard, D. H. (2013). \u2018Knowledge-How and Epistemic Luck\u2019, Nous (Online First. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1111\/nous.12054).","DOI":"10.1111\/nous.12054"},{"key":"2750_CR13","volume-title":"The visual neuroscience of robotic grasping, Achieving sensorimotor skills through dorsal-ventral stream integration","author":"E Chinellato","year":"2015","unstructured":"Chinellato, E., & del Pobil, A. P. (2015). The visual neuroscience of robotic grasping, Achieving sensorimotor skills through dorsal-ventral stream integration. Switzerland: Springer."},{"key":"2750_CR95","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"495","DOI":"10.1215\/00318108-110-4-495","volume":"110","author":"A Clark","year":"2001","unstructured":"Clark, A. (2001). Visual experience and motor action: are the bonds too tight? Philosophical Review, 110, 495\u2013519.","journal-title":"Philosophical Review"},{"key":"2750_CR14","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"205","DOI":"10.5840\/jphil2011108412","volume":"108","author":"M Devitt","year":"2011","unstructured":"Devitt, M. (2011). Methodology and the nature of knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 108, 205\u2013218.","journal-title":"Journal of Philosophy"},{"issue":"3","key":"2750_CR15","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"737","DOI":"10.1111\/j.1933-1592.2012.00638.x","volume":"LXXXV","author":"I Dickie","year":"2012","unstructured":"Dickie, I. (2012). Skill before knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXXXV(3), 737\u2013745.","journal-title":"Philosophy and Phenomenological Research"},{"key":"2750_CR16","volume-title":"Perspectives on embodiment","author":"HL Dreyfus","year":"1996","unstructured":"Dreyfus, H. L. (1996). The current relevance of merleau-ponty\u2019s phenomenology of embodiment. In H. Haber & G. Weiss (Eds.), Perspectives on embodiment. London: Routledge."},{"key":"2750_CR17","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"165","DOI":"10.1016\/S0167-8760(99)00051-3","volume":"35","author":"L Fadiga","year":"2000","unstructured":"Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (2000). Visuomotor neurons: ambiguity of the discharge or \u2018motor\u2019 perception? International Journal of Psychophysiology, 35, 165\u2013177.","journal-title":"International Journal of Psychophysiology"},{"key":"2750_CR18","unstructured":"Fantl, J. (2016) Knowledge How. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta\u00a0(ed.). https:\/\/plato.stanford.edu\/archives\/spr2016\/entries\/knowledge-how\/."},{"issue":"12","key":"2750_CR19","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"3787","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-016-1097-x","volume":"193","author":"G Ferretti","year":"2016","unstructured":"Ferretti, G. (2016a). Pictures, action properties and motor related effects. Synthese, Special Issue: Neuroscience and Its Philosophy, 193(12), 3787\u20133817. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11229-016-1097-x.","journal-title":"Synthese, Special Issue: Neuroscience and Its Philosophy"},{"key":"2750_CR20","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"177","DOI":"10.1016\/j.concog.2016.05.013","volume":"43","author":"G Ferretti","year":"2016","unstructured":"Ferretti, G. (2016b). Through the forest of motor representations. Consciousness and Cognition, 43, 177\u2013196. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1016\/j.concog.2016.05.013.","journal-title":"Consciousness and Cognition"},{"key":"2750_CR21","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1111\/papq.12170","author":"G Ferretti","year":"2016","unstructured":"Ferretti, G. (2016c). Visual feeling of presence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1111\/papq.12170.","journal-title":"Pacific Philosophical Quarterly"},{"key":"2750_CR22","first-page":"179","volume-title":"Model-based reasoning in science and technology. Studies in applied philosophy, epistemology and rational ethics","author":"G Ferretti","year":"2016","unstructured":"Ferretti, G. (2016d). Neurophysiological states and perceptual representations: The case of action properties detected by the ventro-dorsal visual stream. In L. Magnani & C. Casadio (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in science and technology. Studies in applied philosophy, epistemology and rational ethics (Vol. 27, pp. 179\u2013203). Cham: Springer."},{"issue":"3","key":"2750_CR23","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"372","DOI":"10.1017\/apa.2017.28","volume":"3","author":"G Ferretti","year":"2017","unstructured":"Ferretti, G. (2017a). Are pictures peculiar objects of perception? Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 3(3), 372\u2013393. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1017\/apa.2017.28.","journal-title":"Journal of the American Philosophical Association"},{"key":"2750_CR24","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1007\/s11097-017-9533-z","author":"G Ferretti","year":"2017","unstructured":"Ferretti, G. (2017b). Two visual systems in molyneux subjects. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11097-017-9533-z.","journal-title":"Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences"},{"key":"2750_CR25","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1007\/s10670-018-0060-2","author":"G Ferretti","year":"2018","unstructured":"Ferretti, G. (2018). The neural dynamics of seeing-in. Erkenntnis. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s10670-018-0060-2.","journal-title":"Erkenntnis"},{"key":"2750_CR26","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-019-02282-x","author":"G Ferretti","year":"2019","unstructured":"Ferretti, G. (2019). Visual phenomenology versus visuomotor imagery: How can we be aware of action properties? Synthese. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11229-019-02282-x.","journal-title":"Synthese"},{"key":"2750_CR28","unstructured":"Ferretti, G. (Forthcoming). Action at first sight. In Ferretti, G. and Glenney, B. (Eds.). Molyneux\u2019s Question and the History of Philosophy, Routledge."},{"key":"2750_CR29","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1111\/papq.12243","author":"G Ferretti","year":"2018","unstructured":"Ferretti, G., & Zipoli Caiani, S. (2018). Solving the interface problem without translation: The same format thesis. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1111\/papq.12243.","journal-title":"Pacific Philosophical Quarterly"},{"key":"2750_CR30","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-019-02518-w","author":"G Ferretti","year":"2019","unstructured":"Ferretti, G., & Zipoli Caiani, S. (2019). Between vision and action introduction to the special issue. Synthese. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11229-019-02518-w.","journal-title":"Synthese"},{"key":"2750_CR31","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1007\/s11098-012-9994-4","author":"E Fridland","year":"2012","unstructured":"Fridland, E. (2012a). Problems with intellectualism. Philosophical Studies. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11098-012-9994-4.","journal-title":"Philosophical Studies"},{"key":"2750_CR32","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1111\/ejop.12000","author":"E Fridland","year":"2012","unstructured":"Fridland, E. (2012b). Knowing-how: problems and considerations. European Journal of Philosophy. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1111\/ejop.12000.","journal-title":"European Journal of Philosophy"},{"issue":"12","key":"2750_CR33","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"2729","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-014-0411-8","volume":"91","author":"E Fridland","year":"2014","unstructured":"Fridland, E. (2014). They\u2019ve lost control: Reflections on skill. Synthese, 91(12), 2729\u20132750.","journal-title":"Synthese"},{"key":"2750_CR93","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"4337","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-014-0617-9","volume":"194","author":"E Fridland","year":"2015","unstructured":"Fridland, E. (2015). Automatically minded. Synthese, 194, 4337\u20134363. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11229-014-0617-9.","journal-title":"Synthese"},{"issue":"6","key":"2750_CR34","first-page":"1","volume":"174","author":"E Fridland","year":"2016","unstructured":"Fridland, E. (2016). Skill and motor control: Intelligence all the way down. Philosophical Studies, 174(6), 1\u201322.","journal-title":"Philosophical Studies"},{"issue":"5","key":"2750_CR35","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"759","DOI":"10.1080\/09515089.2019.1607275","volume":"32","author":"E Fridland","year":"2019","unstructured":"Fridland, E. (2019). Longer, smaller, faster, stronger: On skills and intelligence. Philosophical Psychology, 32(5), 759\u2013783. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1080\/09515089.2019.1607275.","journal-title":"Philosophical Psychology"},{"key":"2750_CR36","unstructured":"Gallagher, S. (Forthcoming). No yes answers to Molyneux. In Ferretti, G. and Glenney, B. (Eds.). Molyneux\u2019s Question and the History of Philosophy, Routledge."},{"issue":"10","key":"2750_CR37","first-page":"23","volume":"7","author":"V Gallese","year":"2000","unstructured":"Gallese, V. (2000). The inner sense of action. Agency and motor representations. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 7(10), 23\u201340.","journal-title":"Journal of Consciousness Studies"},{"issue":"1","key":"2750_CR38","first-page":"1","volume":"13","author":"V Gallese","year":"2007","unstructured":"Gallese, V. (2007). The \u201cconscious\u201d dorsal stream: Embodied simulation and its role in space and action conscious awareness. Psyche, 13(1), 1\u201320.","journal-title":"Psyche"},{"key":"2750_CR39","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"486","DOI":"10.1007\/s00426-009-0232-4","volume":"73","author":"V Gallese","year":"2009","unstructured":"Gallese, V. (2009). Motor abstraction: a neuroscientic account of how action goals and intentions are mapped and understood. Psychological Research, 73, 486\u2013498.","journal-title":"Psychological Research"},{"issue":"3","key":"2750_CR40","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"365","DOI":"10.1080\/0951508032000121760","volume":"16","author":"V Gallese","year":"2003","unstructured":"Gallese, V., & Metzinger, T. (2003). Motor ontology. The representational reality of goals, actions and selves. Philosophical Psychology, 16(3), 365\u2013388.","journal-title":"Philosophical Psychology"},{"issue":"12","key":"2750_CR41","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"4959","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-016-1184-z","volume":"194","author":"B Gaultier","year":"2017","unstructured":"Gaultier, B. (2017). Skills, procedural knowledge, and knowledge-how. Synthese, 194(12), 4959\u20134981.","journal-title":"Synthese"},{"issue":"1","key":"2750_CR42","first-page":"19","volume":"40","author":"K Hawley","year":"2003","unstructured":"Hawley, K. (2003). Success and knowledge how. American Philosophical Quarterly, 40(1), 19\u201331.","journal-title":"American Philosophical Quarterly"},{"issue":"4","key":"2750_CR43","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"389","DOI":"10.1007\/s11097-005-9001-z","volume":"4","author":"DD Hutto","year":"2005","unstructured":"Hutto, D. D. (2005). Knowing what? Radical versus conservative enactivism. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 389\u2013405.","journal-title":"Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences"},{"key":"2750_CR91","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","unstructured":"Jacob, P., & Jeannerod, M. (2003). Ways of seeing: The scope and limits of visual cognition. Oxford University Press.","DOI":"10.1093\/acprof:oso\/9780198509219.001.0001"},{"key":"2750_CR44","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1093\/acprof:oso\/9780198569657.001.0001","volume-title":"Motor cognition: What actions tell the self","author":"M Jeannerod","year":"2006","unstructured":"Jeannerod, M. (2006). Motor cognition: What actions tell the self. Oxford: Oxford University Press."},{"key":"2750_CR45","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"301","DOI":"10.1016\/j.neuropsychologia.2004.11.016","volume":"43","author":"M Jeannerod","year":"2005","unstructured":"Jeannerod, M., & Jacob, P. (2005). Visual cognition. A new look at the two visual systems model. Neuropsychologia, 43, 301\u2013312.","journal-title":"Neuropsychologia"},{"key":"2750_CR46","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"113","DOI":"10.1007\/s11097-009-9129-3","volume":"9","author":"EM Jung","year":"2010","unstructured":"Jung, E. M., & Newen, A. (2010). Knowledge and abilities: The need for a new understanding of knowing-how. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 113\u2013131. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11097-009-9129-3.","journal-title":"Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences"},{"key":"2750_CR47","volume-title":"Thinking, fast and slow","author":"D Kahneman","year":"2011","unstructured":"Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux."},{"key":"2750_CR48","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-015-0956-1","author":"N Levy","year":"2015","unstructured":"Levy, N. (2015). Embodied savoir-faire: Knowledge-how requires motor representations. Synthese. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11229-015-0956-1.","journal-title":"Synthese"},{"key":"2750_CR49","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","unstructured":"Milner, A., & Goodale, M. (1995\/2006). The visual brain in action (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.","DOI":"10.1093\/acprof:oso\/9780198524724.001.0001"},{"issue":"3","key":"2750_CR50","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"109","DOI":"10.1016\/j.tics.2013.11.006","volume":"18","author":"A Moro","year":"2014","unstructured":"Moro, A. (2014). On the similarity between syntax and actions. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18(3), 109\u2013110.","journal-title":"Trends in Cognitive Sciences"},{"key":"2750_CR51","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1007\/s13164-016-0311-6","author":"M Mylopoulos","year":"2016","unstructured":"Mylopoulos, M., & Pacherie, E. (2016). Intentions and motor representations: The interface challenge. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s13164-016-0311-6.","journal-title":"Review of Philosophy and Psychology"},{"key":"2750_CR52","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","unstructured":"Nanay, B. (2009). Imagining, recognizing and discriminating: Reconsidering the ability hypothesis. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. LXXIX (3).","DOI":"10.1111\/j.1933-1592.2009.00299.x"},{"issue":"3","key":"2750_CR98","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"430","DOI":"10.1111\/j.1468-0378.2010.00407.x","volume":"20","author":"B Nanay","year":"2011","unstructured":"Nanay, B. (2011). Action oriented-perception. European Journal of Philosophy, 20(3), 430\u2013446. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1111\/j.1468-0378.2010.00407.x.","journal-title":"European Journal of Philosophy"},{"key":"2750_CR53","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1093\/acprof:oso\/9780199695379.001.0001","volume-title":"Between perception and action","author":"B Nanay","year":"2013","unstructured":"Nanay, B. (2013). Between perception and action. Oxford: Oxford University Press."},{"issue":"4","key":"2750_CR54","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"278","DOI":"10.1111\/j.1467-8284.2005.00567.x","volume":"65","author":"A No\u00eb","year":"2005","unstructured":"No\u00eb, A. (2005). Against intellectualism. Analysis, 65(4), 278\u2013290. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1111\/j.1467-8284.2005.00567.x.","journal-title":"Analysis"},{"issue":"4","key":"2750_CR55","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"400","DOI":"10.1111\/1468-0017.00142","volume":"15","author":"E Pacherie","year":"2000","unstructured":"Pacherie, E. (2000). The content of intentions. Mind and Language, 15(4), 400\u2013432.","journal-title":"Mind and Language"},{"key":"2750_CR99","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"67","DOI":"10.1027\/1864-9335\/a000044","volume":"42","author":"E Pacherie","year":"2011","unstructured":"Pacherie, E. (2011). Non-conceptual representations for action and the limits of intentional control. Social Psychology, 42, 67\u201373. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1027\/1864-9335\/a000044.","journal-title":"Social Psychology"},{"issue":"175","key":"2750_CR56","first-page":"196","volume":"73","author":"D Papineau","year":"2013","unstructured":"Papineau, D. (2013). In the zone. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 73(175), 196.","journal-title":"Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement"},{"issue":"1","key":"2750_CR57","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"165","DOI":"10.1111\/phis.12045","volume":"25","author":"C Pavese","year":"2015","unstructured":"Pavese, C. (2015a). Knowing a rule. Philosophical Issues, 25(1), 165\u2013188.","journal-title":"Philosophical Issues"},{"issue":"29","key":"2750_CR58","first-page":"1","volume":"15","author":"C Pavese","year":"2015","unstructured":"Pavese, C. (2015b). Practical senses. Philosopher\u2019s Imprint, 15(29), 1\u201325.","journal-title":"Philosopher\u2019s Imprint"},{"issue":"5","key":"2750_CR59","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"784","DOI":"10.1080\/09515089.2019.1612214","volume":"32","author":"C Pavese","year":"2019","unstructured":"Pavese, C. (2019). The psychological reality of practical representation. Philosophical Psychology, 32(5), 784\u2013821. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1080\/09515089.2019.1612214.","journal-title":"Philosophical Psychology"},{"issue":"3","key":"2750_CR60","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"743","DOI":"10.1111\/j.1933-1592.2009.00301.x","volume":"79","author":"T Poston","year":"2009","unstructured":"Poston, T. (2009). Know how to be Gettiered? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79(3), 743\u2013747. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1111\/j.1933-1592.2009.00301.x.","journal-title":"Philosophy and Phenomenological Research"},{"issue":"5","key":"2750_CR61","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"219","DOI":"10.1016\/j.tics.2014.01.001","volume":"18","author":"F Pulverm\u00fcller","year":"2014","unstructured":"Pulverm\u00fcller, F. (2014). The syntax of action. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18(5), 219\u2013220.","journal-title":"Trends in Cognitive Sciences"},{"issue":"2","key":"2750_CR62","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"187","DOI":"10.1111\/j.0268-1064.2006.00311.x","volume":"21","author":"A Raftopoulos","year":"2006","unstructured":"Raftopoulos, A., & M\u00fcller, V. C. (2006). The phenomenal content of experience. Mind and Language, 21(2), 187\u2013219.","journal-title":"Mind and Language"},{"key":"2750_CR63","volume-title":"Mirrors in the brain, How our minds share actions and emotions","author":"G Rizzolatti","year":"2008","unstructured":"Rizzolatti, G., & Sinigaglia, C. (2008). Mirrors in the brain, How our minds share actions and emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press."},{"key":"2750_CR64","volume-title":"The concept of mind","author":"G Ryle","year":"1949","unstructured":"Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson."},{"key":"2750_CR65","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","unstructured":"Schroeder, M. (2012). Showing how to derive knowing how. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. LXXXV (3).","DOI":"10.1111\/j.1933-1592.2012.00639.x"},{"issue":"5","key":"2750_CR66","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"662","DOI":"10.1080\/09515089.2019.1607278","volume":"32","author":"A Schwartz","year":"2019","unstructured":"Schwartz, A., & Drayson, Z. (2019). Intellectualism and the argument from cognitive science. Philosophical Psychology, 32(5), 662\u2013692.","journal-title":"Philosophical Psychology"},{"issue":"3","key":"2750_CR67","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"395","DOI":"10.1007\/s11098-013-0236-1","volume":"170","author":"J Shepherd","year":"2014","unstructured":"Shepherd, J. (2014). The contours of control. Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 395\u2013411.","journal-title":"Philosophical Studies"},{"issue":"3","key":"2750_CR68","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"320","DOI":"10.1111\/mila.12082","volume":"30","author":"J Shepherd","year":"2015","unstructured":"Shepherd, J. (2015). Conscious control over action. Mind and Language, 30(3), 320\u2013344.","journal-title":"Mind and Language"},{"key":"2750_CR69","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1111\/phpr.12433","author":"J Shepherd","year":"2017","unstructured":"Shepherd, J. (2017). Skilled action and the double life of intention. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1111\/phpr.12433.","journal-title":"Philosophy and Phenomenological Research"},{"key":"2750_CR70","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"207","DOI":"10.1111\/j.1468-0068.2010.00758.x","volume":"45","author":"J Stanley","year":"2011","unstructured":"Stanley, J. (2011a). Knowing (How). Nous, 45, 207\u2013238.","journal-title":"Nous"},{"key":"2750_CR71","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1093\/acprof:oso\/9780199695362.001.0001","volume-title":"Know how","author":"J Stanley","year":"2011","unstructured":"Stanley, J. (2011b). Know how. Oxford: Oxford University Press."},{"key":"2750_CR92","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","unstructured":"Stanley, J. (2012). Replies to Dickie, Schroeder and Stalnaker. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXXXV(3).","DOI":"10.1111\/j.1933-1592.2012.00641.x"},{"key":"2750_CR90","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.3389\/fnhum.2013.00503","author":"J Stanley","year":"2013","unstructured":"Stanley, J., & Krakauer, J. W. (2013). Motor skill depends on knowledge of facts. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.3389\/fnhum.2013.00503.","journal-title":"Frontiers in Human Neuroscience"},{"issue":"8","key":"2750_CR72","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"411","DOI":"10.2307\/2678403","volume":"98","author":"J Stanley","year":"2001","unstructured":"Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. The Journal of Philosophy, 98(8), 411\u2013444. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.2307\/2678403.","journal-title":"The Journal of Philosophy"},{"issue":"4","key":"2750_CR73","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"713","DOI":"10.1111\/nous.12144","volume":"51","author":"J Stanley","year":"2017","unstructured":"Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2017). Skill. Nous, 51(4), 713\u2013726. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1111\/nous.12144.","journal-title":"Skill. Nous"},{"key":"2750_CR94","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"17","DOI":"10.1016\/j.concog.2016.05.008","volume":"47","author":"C Teufel","year":"2017","unstructured":"Teufel, C., & Nanay, B. (2017). How to (and how not to) think about top-down influences on visual perception. Consciousness and Cognition, 47, 17\u201325. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1016\/j.concog.2016.05.008.","journal-title":"Consciousness and Cognition"},{"key":"2750_CR74","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","unstructured":"Toribio, J. (2018). Are visuomotor representations cognitively penetrable? Biasing action-guiding vision. Synthese. Special Issue, Between Vision and Action, (Eds.)","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-018-1854-0"},{"key":"2750_CR75","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"541","DOI":"10.1007\/s11097-011-9208-0","volume":"10","author":"C-H Tsai","year":"2011","unstructured":"Tsai, C.-H. (2011). The metaepistemology of knowing-how. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 10, 541\u2013556. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11097-011-9208-0.","journal-title":"Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences"},{"issue":"10","key":"2750_CR96","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"909","DOI":"10.1016\/j.cub.2010.03.058","volume":"20","author":"B-E Verhoef","year":"2010","unstructured":"Verhoef, B.-E., Vogels, R., & Janssen, P. (2010). Contribution of inferior temporal and posterior parietal activity to three-dimensional shape perception. Current Biology, 20(10), 909\u2013913. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1016\/j.cub.2010.03.058.","journal-title":"Current Biology"},{"key":"2750_CR76","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"123","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-006-9103-3","volume":"160","author":"C Wallis","year":"2008","unstructured":"Wallis, C. (2008). Consciousness, context and know-how. Synthese, 160, 123\u2013153.","journal-title":"Synthese"},{"key":"2750_CR77","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"107","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-007-9242-1","volume":"165","author":"JN Williams","year":"2008","unstructured":"Williams, J. N. (2008). Propositional knowledge and know-how. Synthese, 165, 107\u2013125.","journal-title":"Synthese"},{"key":"2750_CR78","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"341","DOI":"10.1007\/s11406-008-9169-x","volume":"37","author":"G Young","year":"2009","unstructured":"Young, G. (2009). Case study evidence for an irreducible form of knowing how to: An argument against a reductive epistemology. Philosophia, 37, 341\u2013360. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11406-008-9169-x.","journal-title":"Philosophia"},{"key":"2750_CR79","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","DOI":"10.1007\/s12136-018-0376-1","author":"G Young","year":"2019","unstructured":"Young, G. (2019). Knowledge How. Procedural knowledge, and the type-token action clause. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s12136-018-0376-1.","journal-title":"Procedural knowledge, and the type-token action clause"},{"key":"2750_CR80","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"275","DOI":"10.1007\/s11097-013-9295-1","volume":"13","author":"S Zipoli Caiani","year":"2013","unstructured":"Zipoli Caiani, S. (2013). Extending the notion of affordance. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 13, 275\u2013293. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11097-013-9295-1.","journal-title":"Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences"},{"key":"2750_CR100","doi-asserted-by":"publisher","first-page":"40","DOI":"10.1016\/j.concog.2016.10.009","volume":"48","author":"S Zipoli Caiani","year":"2017","unstructured":"Zipoli Caiani, S., & Ferretti, G. (2017). Semantic and pragmatic integration in vision for action. Consciousness and Cognition, 48, 40\u201354. https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1016\/j.concog.2016.10.009.","journal-title":"Consciousness and Cognition"}],"container-title":["Synthese"],"original-title":[],"language":"en","link":[{"URL":"https:\/\/link.springer.com\/content\/pdf\/10.1007\/s11229-020-02750-9.pdf","content-type":"application\/pdf","content-version":"vor","intended-application":"text-mining"},{"URL":"https:\/\/link.springer.com\/article\/10.1007\/s11229-020-02750-9\/fulltext.html","content-type":"text\/html","content-version":"vor","intended-application":"text-mining"},{"URL":"https:\/\/link.springer.com\/content\/pdf\/10.1007\/s11229-020-02750-9.pdf","content-type":"application\/pdf","content-version":"vor","intended-application":"similarity-checking"}],"deposited":{"date-parts":[[2021,9,24]],"date-time":"2021-09-24T15:46:44Z","timestamp":1632498404000},"score":1,"resource":{"primary":{"URL":"https:\/\/link.springer.com\/10.1007\/s11229-020-02750-9"}},"subtitle":[],"short-title":[],"issued":{"date-parts":[[2020,7,12]]},"references-count":89,"journal-issue":{"issue":"11","published-print":{"date-parts":[[2021,11]]}},"alternative-id":["2750"],"URL":"https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11229-020-02750-9","relation":{},"ISSN":["0039-7857","1573-0964"],"issn-type":[{"value":"0039-7857","type":"print"},{"value":"1573-0964","type":"electronic"}],"subject":[],"published":{"date-parts":[[2020,7,12]]},"assertion":[{"value":"21 October 2019","order":1,"name":"received","label":"Received","group":{"name":"ArticleHistory","label":"Article History"}},{"value":"15 June 2020","order":2,"name":"accepted","label":"Accepted","group":{"name":"ArticleHistory","label":"Article History"}},{"value":"12 July 2020","order":3,"name":"first_online","label":"First Online","group":{"name":"ArticleHistory","label":"Article History"}}]}}