{"status":"ok","message-type":"work","message-version":"1.0.0","message":{"indexed":{"date-parts":[[2022,10,31]],"date-time":"2022-10-31T08:28:01Z","timestamp":1667204881333},"reference-count":50,"publisher":"Springer Science and Business Media LLC","issue":"6","license":[{"start":{"date-parts":[[2015,7,3]],"date-time":"2015-07-03T00:00:00Z","timestamp":1435881600000},"content-version":"tdm","delay-in-days":0,"URL":"http:\/\/www.springer.com\/tdm"}],"funder":[{"DOI":"10.13039\/100000925","name":"John Templeton Foundation","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","award":["36093"],"id":[{"id":"10.13039\/100000925","id-type":"DOI","asserted-by":"crossref"}]}],"content-domain":{"domain":["link.springer.com"],"crossmark-restriction":false},"short-container-title":["Synthese"],"published-print":{"date-parts":[[2016,6]]},"DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-015-0811-4","type":"journal-article","created":{"date-parts":[[2015,7,2]],"date-time":"2015-07-02T10:51:08Z","timestamp":1435834268000},"page":"1817-1832","update-policy":"http:\/\/dx.doi.org\/10.1007\/springer_crossmark_policy","source":"Crossref","is-referenced-by-count":5,"title":["Nested explanation in Aristotle and Mayr"],"prefix":"10.1007","volume":"193","author":[{"ORCID":"http:\/\/orcid.org\/0000-0003-1217-5476","authenticated-orcid":false,"given":"Lucas","family":"Mix","sequence":"first","affiliation":[]}],"member":"297","published-online":{"date-parts":[[2015,7,3]]},"reference":[{"key":"811_CR1","unstructured":"Baker, J. R. (1938). The evolution of breeding seasons. In G. R. de Beer (Ed.), Evolution: Essays on aspects of evolutionary biology. (pp. 161\u2013177). Oxford: Oxford Press."},{"key":"811_CR2","volume-title":"Aristotle\u2019s posterior analytics","author":"J Barnes","year":"1975","unstructured":"Barnes, J. (1975). Aristotle\u2019s posterior analytics. Oxford: Oxford University Press."},{"key":"811_CR3","volume-title":"The complete works of Aristotle, the revised Oxford translation","year":"1984","unstructured":"Barnes, J. (Ed.). (1984). The complete works of Aristotle, the revised Oxford translation. Princeton: Princeton University Press."},{"key":"811_CR4","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"712","DOI":"10.1016\/j.tree.2013.09.013","volume":"28","author":"P Bateson","year":"2013","unstructured":"Bateson, P., & Laland, K. N. (2013). Tinbergen\u2019s four questions: An appreciation and an update. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 28, 712\u2013718.","journal-title":"Trends in Ecology and Evolution"},{"key":"811_CR5","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","DOI":"10.7551\/mitpress\/8921.001.0001","volume-title":"From groups to individuals","author":"F Bouchard","year":"2013","unstructured":"Bouchard, F., & Huneman, P. (2013). From groups to individuals. Cambridge: MIT."},{"key":"811_CR6","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"767","DOI":"10.1007\/s10539-013-9367-1","volume":"28","author":"B Calcott","year":"2013","unstructured":"Calcott, B. (2013). Why how and why aren\u2019t enough: More problems with Mayr\u2019s proximate-ultimate distinction. Biology and Philosophy, 28, 767\u2013780.","journal-title":"Biology and Philosophy"},{"key":"811_CR7","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"10061","DOI":"10.1073\/pnas.0904433106","volume":"106","author":"DC Dennett","year":"2009","unstructured":"Dennett, D. C. (2009). Darwin\u2019s \u201cstrange inversion of reasoning\u201d. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 106, 10061\u201310065.","journal-title":"Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA"},{"key":"811_CR8","first-page":"47","volume-title":"Contemporary philosophical naturalism and its implications","author":"DC Dennett","year":"2014","unstructured":"Dennett, D. C. (2014). The evolution of reasons. In B. Bashour & H. D. Muller (Eds.), Contemporary philosophical naturalism and its implications (pp. 47\u201362). New York: Routledge."},{"key":"811_CR9","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"189","DOI":"10.1016\/S0376-6357(99)00035-2","volume":"46","author":"D Dewsbury","year":"1999","unstructured":"Dewsbury, D. (1999). The proximate and the ultimate: Past, present, and future. Behavioural Processes, 46, 189\u2013199.","journal-title":"Behavioural Processes"},{"key":"811_CR10","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"401","DOI":"10.1007\/BF02207379","volume":"5","author":"RC Francis","year":"1990","unstructured":"Francis, R. C. (1990). Causes, proximate and ultimate. Biology and Philosophy, 5, 401\u2013415.","journal-title":"Biology and Philosophy"},{"key":"811_CR11","first-page":"217","volume-title":"Doubt and dogmatism","author":"M Frede","year":"1980","unstructured":"Frede, M. (1980). The original notion of cause. In M. Schofield, M. Burnyeat, & J. Barnes (Eds.), Doubt and dogmatism (pp. 217\u2013249). Clarendon Press: Oxford."},{"key":"811_CR12","first-page":"226","volume":"30","author":"A Gotthelf","year":"1976","unstructured":"Gotthelf, A. (1976). Aristotle\u2019s conception of final causality. Review of Metaphysics, 30, 226\u2013254.","journal-title":"Review of Metaphysics"},{"key":"811_CR13","volume-title":"Philosophical issues in Aristotle\u2019s biology","year":"1987","unstructured":"Gotthelf, A., & Lennox, J. G. (Eds.). (1987). Philosophical issues in Aristotle\u2019s biology. New York: Cambridge University Press."},{"key":"811_CR14","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"799","DOI":"10.1098\/rspb.1999.0708","volume":"266","author":"A Grafen","year":"1999","unstructured":"Grafen, A. (1999). Formal Darwinism, the individual-as-maximizing-agent analogy and bet-hedging. Proceedings of the Royal Society London B: Biological Sciences, 266, 799\u2013803.","journal-title":"Proceedings of the Royal Society London B: Biological Sciences"},{"key":"811_CR15","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"581","DOI":"10.1098\/rspb.1979.0086","volume":"205","author":"SJ Gould","year":"1979","unstructured":"Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 205, 581\u2013598.","journal-title":"Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences"},{"key":"811_CR16","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"415","DOI":"10.1007\/s10539-006-9033-y","volume":"22","author":"D Haig","year":"2007","unstructured":"Haig, D. (2007). Weismann rules! OK? Epigenetics and the Lamarckian temptation. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 415\u2013428.","journal-title":"Biology and Philosophy"},{"key":"811_CR17","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"461","DOI":"10.1007\/s10539-012-9315-5","volume":"27","author":"D Haig","year":"2012","unstructured":"Haig, D. (2012). The strategic gene. Biology and Philosophy, 27, 461\u2013479.","journal-title":"Biology and Philosophy"},{"key":"811_CR18","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"781","DOI":"10.1007\/s10539-013-9369-z","volume":"28","author":"D Haig","year":"2013","unstructured":"Haig, D. (2013). Proximate and ultimate causes: How come? and what for? Biology and Philosophy, 28, 781\u2013786.","journal-title":"Biology and Philosophy"},{"key":"811_CR19","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"675","DOI":"10.1007\/s10539-014-9432-4","volume":"29","author":"D Haig","year":"2014","unstructured":"Haig, D. (2014). Fighting the good cause. Biology and Philosophy, 29, 675\u2013697.","journal-title":"Biology and Philosophy"},{"key":"811_CR20","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"354","DOI":"10.1086\/497114","volume":"97","author":"WD Hamilton","year":"1963","unstructured":"Hamilton, W. D. (1963). The evolution of altruistic behavior. The American Naturalist, 97, 354\u2013356.","journal-title":"The American Naturalist"},{"key":"811_CR21","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","DOI":"10.1093\/0199285306.001.0001","volume-title":"Aristotle on teleology","author":"MR Johnson","year":"2005","unstructured":"Johnson, M. R. (2005). Aristotle on teleology. Oxford: Clarendon."},{"key":"811_CR22","unstructured":"Lahti, D. C. (2014). Response. In W. R. Thorson (Ed.), The woodpecker\u2019s purpose: A critique of intelligent design. (pp. 135\u2013142) Wenham, MA: Center for Faith and Inquiry at Gordon College."},{"key":"811_CR23","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"1512","DOI":"10.1126\/science.1210879","volume":"334","author":"KN Laland","year":"2011","unstructured":"Laland, K. N., Sterelny, K., Odling-Smee, J., Hoppitt, W., & Uller, T. (2011). Cause and effect in biology revisited: Is Mayr\u2019s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science, 334, 1512\u20131516.","journal-title":"Science"},{"key":"811_CR24","volume-title":"The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy","author":"J Lennox","year":"2014","unstructured":"Lennox, J. (2014). Aristotle\u2019s biology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press."},{"key":"811_CR25","first-page":"183","volume-title":"Interpreting Aristotle\u2019s posterior analytics in late antiquity and beyond","author":"M Leunissen","year":"2010","unstructured":"Leunissen, M. (2010a). Aristotle and Philoponus on final causes in scientific demonstrations in APo. II.11\u2019. In F. A. J. de Haas, M. Leunissen, & M. Martijn (Eds.), Interpreting Aristotle\u2019s posterior analytics in late antiquity and beyond (pp. 183\u2013201). London: Brill."},{"issue":"4","key":"811_CR26","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"117","DOI":"10.1515\/APEIRON.2010.43.4.117","volume":"43","author":"M Leunissen","year":"2010","unstructured":"Leunissen, M. (2010b). Nature as a good housekeeper: Secondary teleology and material necessity in Aristotle\u2019s biology. Apeiron, 43(4), 117\u2013142.","journal-title":"Apeiron"},{"key":"811_CR27","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"325","DOI":"10.1163\/156852810X523914","volume":"55","author":"M Leunissen","year":"2010","unstructured":"Leunissen, M., & Gotthelf, A. (2010). What\u2019s teleology got to do with it: A reinterpretation of Aristotle\u2019s generation of animals V. Phronesis, 55, 325\u2013356.","journal-title":"Phronesis"},{"key":"811_CR28","volume-title":"Major transitions in evolution","author":"J Maynard Smith","year":"1995","unstructured":"Maynard Smith, J., & Szathm\u00e1ry, E. (1995). Major transitions in evolution. Oxford: Oxford Press."},{"key":"811_CR29","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"1501","DOI":"10.1126\/science.134.3489.1501","volume":"134","author":"E Mayr","year":"1961","unstructured":"Mayr, E. (1961). Cause and effect in biology: Kinds of causes, predictability, and teleology are viewed by a practicing biologist. Science, 134, 1501\u20131506.","journal-title":"Science"},{"key":"811_CR30","volume-title":"The growth of biological thought: Diversity, evolution, and inheritance","author":"E Mayr","year":"1982","unstructured":"Mayr, E. (1982). The growth of biological thought: Diversity, evolution, and inheritance. Cambridge: Harvard University Press."},{"key":"811_CR31","volume-title":"Toward a new philosophy of biology, observations of an evolutionist","author":"E Mayr","year":"1988","unstructured":"Mayr, E. (1988). Toward a new philosophy of biology, observations of an evolutionist. Cambridge: Harvard."},{"key":"811_CR32","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"117","DOI":"10.2307\/2709913","volume":"53","author":"E Mayr","year":"1992","unstructured":"Mayr, E. (1992). The idea of teleology. Journal of the History of Ideas, 53, 117\u2013135.","journal-title":"Journal of the History of Ideas"},{"key":"811_CR33","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"93","DOI":"10.1007\/BF00868508","volume":"8","author":"E Mayr","year":"1993","unstructured":"Mayr, E. (1993). Proximate and ultimate causations. Biology and Philosophy, 8, 93\u201394.","journal-title":"Biology and Philosophy"},{"key":"811_CR34","first-page":"3","volume":"6","author":"LJ Mix","year":"2014","unstructured":"Mix, L. J. (2014). Proper activity, preference, and the meaning of life. Philosophy and Theory in Biology, 6, 3\u20139.","journal-title":"Philosophy and Theory in Biology"},{"key":"811_CR35","volume-title":"Chance and necessity","author":"J Monod","year":"1971","unstructured":"Monod, J. (1971). Chance and necessity. New York: Random House."},{"key":"811_CR36","first-page":"127","volume-title":"Whatever happened to the soul? Scientific and theological portraits of human nature","author":"N Murphy","year":"1998","unstructured":"Murphy, N. (1998). Nonreductive physicalism: Philosophical issues. In W. S. Brown, N. Murphy, & H. N. Maloney (Eds.), Whatever happened to the soul? Scientific and theological portraits of human nature (pp. 127\u2013148). Minneapolis: Fortress."},{"key":"811_CR37","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"681","DOI":"10.1016\/j.tree.2013.10.008","volume":"28","author":"RM Nesse","year":"2013","unstructured":"Nesse, R. M. (2013). Tinbergen\u2019s four questions, organized: A response to Bateson and Laland. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 28, 681\u2013682.","journal-title":"Trends in Ecology and Evolution"},{"key":"811_CR38","volume-title":"Persons and causes: The metaphysics of free will","author":"T O\u2019Connor","year":"2000","unstructured":"O\u2019Connor, T. (2000). Persons and causes: The metaphysics of free will. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers."},{"key":"811_CR39","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","DOI":"10.1017\/CBO9780511529269","volume-title":"Divine will and the mechanical philosophy","author":"MJ Osler","year":"1994","unstructured":"Osler, M. J. (1994). Divine will and the mechanical philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press."},{"key":"811_CR40","first-page":"390","volume-title":"Behavior and evolution","author":"CS Pittendrigh","year":"1958","unstructured":"Pittendrigh, C. S. (1958). Adaptation, natural selection and behavior. In A. Roe & G. G. Simpson (Eds.), Behavior and evolution (pp. 390\u2013416). New Haven: Yale."},{"key":"811_CR41","volume-title":"Progress in evolution and meaning in life","author":"WB Provine","year":"1988","unstructured":"Provine, W. B. (1988). Progress in evolution and meaning in life. Chicago: University of Chicago."},{"key":"811_CR42","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","DOI":"10.1093\/actrade\/9780199244959.book.1","volume-title":"Aristotle\u2019s prior and posterior analytics","author":"WD Ross","year":"1949","unstructured":"Ross, W. D. (1949). Aristotle\u2019s prior and posterior analytics. Oxford: Clarendon."},{"key":"811_CR43","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","DOI":"10.2307\/j.ctv1kz4gtk","volume-title":"Monad to man, the concept of progress in evolutionary biology","author":"M Ruse","year":"2009","unstructured":"Ruse, M. (2009). Monad to man, the concept of progress in evolutionary biology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press."},{"key":"811_CR44","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","DOI":"10.4324\/9780203961940","volume-title":"Aristotle","author":"C Shields","year":"2007","unstructured":"Shields, C. (2007). Aristotle. New York: Routledge."},{"key":"811_CR45","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"103","DOI":"10.1007\/s11229-011-9878-8","volume":"185","author":"C Shields","year":"2012","unstructured":"Shields, C. (2012). The dialectic of life. Synthese, 185, 103\u2013124.","journal-title":"Synthese"},{"key":"811_CR46","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","DOI":"10.1017\/CBO9780511806285","volume-title":"Evidence and evolution, the logic behind the science","author":"E Sober","year":"2008","unstructured":"Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution, the logic behind the science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press."},{"key":"811_CR47","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"123","DOI":"10.1111\/eth.12192","volume":"120","author":"JE Strassmann","year":"2013","unstructured":"Strassmann, J. E. (2013). Tribute to Tinbergen: The place of animal behavior in biology. Ethology, 120, 123\u2013126.","journal-title":"Ethology"},{"key":"811_CR48","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"410","DOI":"10.1111\/j.1439-0310.1963.tb01161.x","volume":"20","author":"N Tinbergen","year":"1963","unstructured":"Tinbergen, N. (1963). On aims and methods of ethology. Zeitschrift f\u00fcr Tierpsychologie, 20, 410\u2013433.","journal-title":"Zeitschrift f\u00fcr Tierpsychologie"},{"key":"811_CR49","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"425","DOI":"10.1093\/bjps\/axl001","volume":"57","author":"D Walsh","year":"2006","unstructured":"Walsh, D. (2006). Evolutionary essentialism. British Journal of the Philosophy of Science, 57, 425\u2013448.","journal-title":"British Journal of the Philosophy of Science"},{"key":"811_CR50","doi-asserted-by":"crossref","first-page":"737","DOI":"10.1038\/171737a0","volume":"171","author":"JD Watson","year":"1953","unstructured":"Watson, J. D., & Crick, F. H. (1953). Molecular structure of nucleic acids: A structure for deoxyribose nucleic acid. Nature, 171, 737\u2013738.","journal-title":"Nature"}],"container-title":["Synthese"],"original-title":[],"language":"en","link":[{"URL":"http:\/\/link.springer.com\/content\/pdf\/10.1007\/s11229-015-0811-4.pdf","content-type":"application\/pdf","content-version":"vor","intended-application":"text-mining"},{"URL":"http:\/\/link.springer.com\/article\/10.1007\/s11229-015-0811-4\/fulltext.html","content-type":"text\/html","content-version":"vor","intended-application":"text-mining"},{"URL":"http:\/\/link.springer.com\/content\/pdf\/10.1007\/s11229-015-0811-4","content-type":"unspecified","content-version":"vor","intended-application":"similarity-checking"}],"deposited":{"date-parts":[[2022,5,16]],"date-time":"2022-05-16T19:10:21Z","timestamp":1652728221000},"score":1,"resource":{"primary":{"URL":"http:\/\/link.springer.com\/10.1007\/s11229-015-0811-4"}},"subtitle":[],"short-title":[],"issued":{"date-parts":[[2015,7,3]]},"references-count":50,"journal-issue":{"issue":"6","published-print":{"date-parts":[[2016,6]]}},"alternative-id":["811"],"URL":"https:\/\/doi.org\/10.1007\/s11229-015-0811-4","relation":{},"ISSN":["0039-7857","1573-0964"],"issn-type":[{"value":"0039-7857","type":"print"},{"value":"1573-0964","type":"electronic"}],"subject":[],"published":{"date-parts":[[2015,7,3]]}}}